James R. Stoner
Is There a Political Philosophy in the
Declaration of Independence?
Is there a political philosophy in the Dec-
laration of Independence? One step toward
answering this question—not the only
step,
but from the philosopher's point of view
the most fundamental—is to ask whether
the "self-evident truths" of the Declaration
are really true after all. Another way of
putting it, which I once saw in a conference
title,
is to ask whether the "self-evident
truths"
are fact or fiction.
I have to admit that "fact or fiction"
struck me at first
as
an odd
way
of question-
ing the authenticity of
truths,
but on reflec-
tion I decided it
was a
particularly felicitous
turn of phrase. Living in a pragmatic age,
we tend to equate fact with truth, and fic-
tion with falsehood. There is something
characteristically American about such a
way of thinking. Still, it is important at the
outset to recognize that this frame of mind
is not universal. No less an authority than
Aristotle writes that fiction (poetry) is
"more philosophic and more serious" than
fact (history), because it speaks of univer-
sals rather than particulars; there is more
truth in understanding the soul of a man
like Homer's Odysseus than in knowing, to
quote Aristotle, what "Alcibiades did or
had done to him"'—or even, did not do or
have done to him, as students of Plato's
Symposium
will understand.
I
will return to
the question of fact and its relation to truth.
but my point at the outset is that part of the
question of whether there is a political phi-
losophy in the Declaration is whether what
the Declaration proclaims as self-evident
truths really are true.
But that is not the whole of the question.
As others have pointed out, the Declara-
tion does not say, "These truths are
self-
evident...." It says, instead, that "we hold"
them to be so. If
we
understand "philoso-
phy" as it is often understood, in the sense
of a doctrine, and if we understand "politi-
cal philosophy" as political science depart-
ments often do, as a synonym for political
theory, then the question of whether there
is a political philosophy in the Declaration
is the question of whether the Declaration
binds us to a particular political creed.
I say "binds" because the Declaration is
treated, even today, as authoritative law in
one sense: It is printed at the head of the
United
States
Code,
where it is considered
the first of our organic laws. More to the
point, politically today the Declaration of
Independence has no open
enemies;
it
is
the
touchstone of our political arguments rather
than an object of advocacy any more. Even
James
R.
Stoner
is
Professor
of
Political
Science
at
Louisiana
State
University,
and he
serves
as a
member
of the
National Council
for the
Humanities.
His
most
recent
book
is
Common
Law
Liberty
(2003).
THE
INTERCOLLEGIATE
REVIEW—Fall/Winter2005
Is There a Political Philosophy in the Declaration of Independence?
by James
R.
Stoner
those who dismiss the American founders
as racist or sexist want to keep the Declara-
tion. They accuse the founders of hypocrisy
rather than mistaken principle.
It is not
only that no one wants to be on the wrong
side
of
the Declaration,
but
that even
the
charges made against
the
Declaration's
authors seem
to be
anchored
in the
Declaration's
own
principle
of
equality.
V\^ether or not that principle and the other
purported truths that accompany
it are
true,
they would seem in fact to be the first
principles
of
our regime.
And this leads to my third concern. If the
"self-evident truths" of the Declaration are
either true
or
fundamentally ours,
how
should they affect our political life? While
loyalty to the original Constitution is often
dismissed
as
hopelessly anachronistic
or
conservative, loyalty
to the
Declaration
might seem
to
have
the
opposite conse-
quence:
to mandate support of those move-
ments that seek
to
extend the reach of equal-
ity in America. Abraham Lincoln seems
to
have thought so. He wrote that the asser-
tion
of
human equality
in
the Declaration
provides
"a
standard maxim
for
free soci-
ety, which should
be
familiar
to all, and
revered
by
all; constantly looked
to, con-
stantly labored for, and even though never
perfectly attained, constantly approxi-
mated,
and
thereby constantly spreading
and deepening its influence, and augment-
ing
the
happiness
and
value
of
life
to all
people
of all
colors everywhere."^
At the
very least, Lincoln's use of the Declaration's
principle
of
equality
in the
controversy
over slavery
set a
precedent
for its use to
reform the regime from within.
Still, however important Lincoln's
achievement
or
however appropriate
the
use
of the
Declaration
in its
support
Jefferson himself understood
the
implica-
tions
of
his principles
for the
question
of
slavery,
as
evidenced
by the
clause
con-
demning the slave trade that he would have
included but that Congress cut out—it still
ought
to be
legitimate
to
ask whether
the
Declaration today commits Americans to
a
particular program
of
development.
These then are my questions.
I
want
to
ask whether the self-evident truths are true,
whether we believe they are,
and
how we
ought to act on them. First, however,
I
want
to
ask
what they mean
and to
answer
by
paying attention
to the
document
as a
whole.
The Short Version and the Long
buppose the Declaration had been vwitten
as
it
is usually read today. It would be only
about
a
page
in
length, edited down
to
the
first
two
paragraphs and then the
last,
where
the actual declaration
of
independence
is
made. No one would deny that these para-
graphs—especially the famous second one,
with its elegantly simple account of the first
principles
of
natural rights
and
just
gov-
ernment—contain
the
most memorable
phrases
in
the document, indeed precisely
the phrases that have fired the imagination
of generations of Americans and of reform-
ers
and
revolutionaries around
the
globe.
Nor is
it
only frequent repetition that gives
these phrases their ring
of
self-evidence,
even several centuries after they were
penned. Jefferson crafted them with care,
and he drew upon a rich tradition of politi-
cal theory that had developed in the previ-
ous century
or so in
England, most espe-
cially
as
conveyed
in the
Two
Treatises
of
Government
by John Locke.
Though echoes
of
Locke's phraseology
can
be
heard
in
Jefferson's language,
Jefferson claimed that the Declaration
did
not reflect any single man's ideas but rather
"the harmonizing sentiments
of
the
day,
whether expressed
in
conversation,
in let-
ters,
printed essays,
or in the
elementary
books
of
public right, as Aristotle, Cicero,
Locke, Sidney, etc."' Insisting that political
THE INTERCOLLEGIATE
REVIEW—Fall/Winter2005
Is There a Political Philosophy in the Declaration of Independence?
by James
R.
Stoner
reflection must begin with equal natural
rights,
that government
is
itself not natu-
rally given but rather
is
formed through the
consent
of
those who acknowledge
it,
that
government has the limited purpose of
se-
curing rights,
and
that abusive govern-
ment can be cashiered, the theoretical para-
graph
of
the Declaration sketches
a
politi-
cal doctrine that today
we
recognize
as
classically liberal—in contradistinction,
I
might
add,
despite Jefferson's claim,
to
Aristotle's teaching that the polis exists by
nature and has the promotion of virtue
as
its highest end. Whether
out of
personal
conviction
or
because liberty cannot
be
secure unless the people believe—remem-
ber his famous remark
a
decade later, "can
the liberties
of
a nation
be
thought secure
when we have removed their only firm ba-
sis,
a
conviction in the minds of the people
that these liberties
are
of
the
gift of
God?""
Jefferson states more clearly than Locke
that what
I
have called equal natural rights
are an endowment of the Creator, presum-
ably the same "Nature's God" mentioned
in the Declaration's first sentence. But that
government itself has
a
human rather than
a divine origin
is
clear. Indeed,
in a
sense,
that
is the
whole point—for
the
Declara-
tion
is
written
to
justify^ political change.
Still, the famous paragraphs of the Dec-
laration are but a part of the
whole.
Looked
at
by an
age enamored
of
political theory
and ideology, they appear
to be its
most
important passages; but at the center of the
document is a list of grievances against the
king and Parliament that make the case
for
independence there
and
then. These
are,
the Declaration says, "Facts...submitted
to
a candid World" to "prove" that the British
are intent upon "the Establishment
of
an
absolute Tyranny over these States."
These central passages
of the
Declaration's bill of indictment are conve-
niently grouped in three divisions. The first
is concerned with constitutional violations
and abuses of constitutional powers by the
king. Here, twelve different complaints are
lodged, accusing the king of threatening the
public good by the use of
his
veto, dissolv-
ing colonial assemblies, obstructing
jus-
tice,
keeping standing armies among them
in peacetime, and the like. The thirteenth
grievance introduces the second division,
the "Acts of pretended legislation" that the
king has passed by "combin[ing] with oth-
ers to subject us to a Jurisdiction foreign to
our Constitution,
and
unacknowledged
by
our
Laws." Referred
to
here
are
nine
acts of Parliament, described not by name
but by their effects—imposing taxes with-
out consent, suspending trial by jury, abol-
ishing colonial charters, and
so
forth.
Fi-
nally, there are five statements introduced
by an implicit reference to the King's Proc-
lamation
of
Rebellion of August 23, 1775,
under which
"He has
abdicated Govern-
ment here, by declaring us out of
his
Pro-
tection and waging War against us." Here,
his acts
of
war
are
summarized
and de-
nounced.
From the point of view of the theoretical
paragraphs with their "self-evident truths,"
these many statements in the middle of the
Declaration
are the
"facts" which prove
that the king has in mind
a
despotism over
America and that
the
colonists
had
better
act
now.
As a reading of the middle section,
this is sound, but not sufficient. To be sure,
if revolution has
to be
made
for a
reason,
then there has
to
be
a
way of proving that
the king
is
becoming tyrannical; this is pre-
cisely what the various facts
are
meant
to
show. But unlike the first principles of
poli-
tics,
the
tyranny
in
these rather general
facts—which never name names or dates or
places—is
not
immediately self-evident.
The outrage comes from a hidden premise:
the English constitutional tradition,
or at
least the common law rights and liberties of
that tradition, which the Americans claim
as their rightfiil heritage.
THE INTERCOLLEGIATE
REVIEW—Fall/Winter2005
Is There a Political Philosophy in the Declaration of Independence?
by James
R.
Stoner
What
is
Not Self-Evident
about the Self-Evident Truths
Here is the source of
the
principle of no
taxation without representation, the inde-
pendence of the judiciary, trial by jury, the
priority
of
civil
to
military authority,
and i
he self-evident truths of the Declaration,
much else. That scholars today
no
longer
tend to read these parts of the Declaration
h
CONGRESS,
Jctrj.
is some measure
of
how
far
we
have lost touch v«th
that tradition,
but
that
does
not
mean
the
com-
plaints were not taken se-
riously
by our
founding
generation. To speak only
of
the
federal level, nearly
every grievance detailed in
the Declaration
is ad-
dressed and prevented by
a specific provision of the
Constitution and the Bill
of
Rights.
The bill
of griev-
ances,
in
other
words,
adds
gravity
and
substance
to
the abstract principles formulated
in the
"self-evident truths,"
and
thus guards
against arbitrary recourse
to
rebellion.
The Declaration justifies
a
political revo-
lution,
to be
sure,
but the
constitutional
dispute with England gave
our
revolution
its distinctive form
and
contributed
to its
success. That revolution was
not
without
its lawless moments,
but on the
whole
its
spirit was to reinvigorate old forms of
self-
governance and to reinforce protection
for
property and social order.
Its
self-evident
first principles were soon to challenge some
of
these
forms—restrictions on the suffrage,
for example,
and in
some
of the
states,
slavery, itself unknown
at
common law
but
it is no
more
an
accident that these
challenges were approached
in a
spirit
of
constitutional compromise than that
the
revolution culminated
in a
Constitution.
There, after
all,
in the middle division of the
middle part of the Declaration, is mention
of an unwritten "Constitution" which
the
Americans
already
assert
to be
their own.
then, garner much of their specific political
significance
for the
American Revolution
from the evidence offered
by
the
facts
of
Anglo-
American constitutional-
ism; these measure the
vio-
lations (and later
the
rem-
edies)
as
well as moderate
the radical potential in the
revolutionary language
taken
by
itself.
Stripped
of this context,
the
first
principles enunciated
by
Jefferson are not self-evi-
dent
at
all—at least,
not
to anyone raised
in the
tradition
of
Western vir-
tue
or in a
world formed
by Judeo-Christian
belief.
Let
me
give
an
example. The "self-evi-
dent truths," it seems to me, do not give an
adequate account of
the
family, the funda-
mental institution of social life. First, what-
ever might
be
said
of
the relation
of
hus-
band and
wife,
the family
is
built not around
equality, but around the inequality of par-
ent and
child.
Precisely the most basic mean-
ing
of
Jefferson's statement
of
equality
that
no man is the
natural ruler
or the
natural subject
of
another—is not true
of
this relation,
for
the parents are surely the
natural rulers of their dependent children.
Second, the family
is
first and foremost not
about rights,
but
about duties; even
the
right
of
children
to
care
and
education
is
abstract and vague compared to the duty of
parents
to
provide
and
instruct
and the
duty
of
children
to
obey and learn. Third,
the origin
of
the family is not exactly con-
sent.
In
some cultures, including our own,
spouses choose
for
themselves whom
to
marry, but even then the roles they assume
THE INTERCOLLEGIATE
REVIEW—Fa/Z/Mnter2005
Is There a Political Philosophy in the Declaration of Independence?
by James
R.
Stoner
are largely socially defined. Except
in
cases
of adoption, and very rarely then, children
do
not
choose their parents,
and
(leaving
aside brave, new technologies and, again,
adoption) parents do not choose their chil-
dren. Fourth, the end of the family is only
incidentally the security of
rights;
it is prin-
cipally provision
and
nurture
in an
envi-
ronment formed by love. And fifth, when
family becomes destructive
of
its ends,
it
cannot be altered and abolished without in
most instances inflicting further wounds
that never heal.
Now about this counter-example
to the
self-evident truths
of
the Declaration,
al-
low me to make two points. First, Jefferson
and his fellows were altogether aware that
families were not formed upon their prin-
ciples.
Precisely what they objected
to in
Tory political theory
was
political
patriarchalism, the effort
to
form the state
on analogy to the family. Natural equality
meant that the king was not to act as father
in relation
to
his people—not that fathers
were not
kings
in their own
homes.
Govern-
ment by consent meant that the command-
ment
to
honor one's father
and
mother
could not be invoked by a political nobility
demanding homage. That abusive govern-
ment can
be
changed
was
not seen to under-
mine
the
indissolubility
of
marriage
nor
the lifelong attachment between parent and
child.
But secondly, there
is no
denying that,
since as long
ago
as John Locke's Two
Trea-
tises
and even Thomas Hobbes's Leviathan,
liberal philosophers have sought
to
recon-
ceive
the
family
on
liberal terms,
and of
course
in
our own day a vast social experi-
ment has been undertaken
to
remodel
the
family
on
egalitarian principles and
to re-
orient authority vwthin
it on the
basis
of
consent. Though opinions about
the
suc-
cess of this effort are bound to differ, allow
me to say for my own part that
I
am more
impressed by the resilience of old patterns
against
all the
force
of
dominant opinion
than
I
am by evidence that abuses
have
been
diminished
and
familial happiness more
commonly achieved.
The
fundamental
equality
of
the sexes may
be
self-evident,
but their equality in the sense of their hav-
ing
no
relevant differences even from
the
point of view of the family
is
not.
And unless
one
is
driven
by a
personal
or
ideological
commitment
to
non-traditional family
forms,
I
do not see how one can argue that
the current regime vnth regard to the fam-
ily
in
W^estern society
is
self-evidently
the
best,
at
least with respect
to
children. One
might note that almost nowhere
in the
West today
are
native populations even
reproducing their numbers,
and in
some
countries those populations
are
on the verge
of precipitous
decline.
It
is a
matter in which
we certainly need,
and all
have difficulty
sorting through,
the
facts.
What, Then,
Is
Self-Evidently True?
iVLy point
in
raising the counter-example
of the family is
not to
deny that what
the
Declaration calls self-evident truths are
true,
but
to
show, first, the grounds that might
be raised
in
objection
to
them (and so,
I
concede,
to caU
into question their
self-
evidence), and second, to suggest how they
need
to be
understood
so as not to
place
their authors under the charge of hopeless
contradiction.
Of course
a
contradiction between
our
founders' words
and
practices was much
noted and commented on
in
the country's
first four-score years and seven in regard to
the institution of slavery. Justice can hardly
be done to this topic in
a
brief mention, but
I would say that on the whole the founders
recognized
the
contradiction
and
hoped,
in Lincoln's terms, that they
had
placed
slavery on a course of ultimate extinction
even though they excised
the
condemna-
tion of slavery from Jefferson's draft. W^hen
THE INTERCOLLEGIATE
REVIEW—Fall/Winter2005
Is There a Political Philosophy in the Declaration
of
Independence?
by James
R,
Stoner
a generation came along that defended sla-
very
as a
positive good, that generation
either denounced the Declaration or inter-
preted
its
universal language
in
narrow
ways.
With regard to the family, however, I see
no contradiction within
the
Declaration's
theory, though perhaps there
is a
certain
ambiguity.
It
is easy enough to understand
the pressure
of
analogy that would make
the hierarchical family entail
an
authori-
tarian state,
or
make
an
egalitarian state
demand
an
egalitarian family.
But it
also
makes sense
to
see the relation as,
I
would
argue, our founding fathers did: The patri-
archal state
had to go
because
it
makes
children
of
real fathers, refusing
to
allow
them the manly responsibility of governing
themselves and those with whose care they
are charged. In this
way,
the issue resembles
the related theological question
of
God's
kingship. On the one hand, divine kingship
might seem
to
entail
by
analogy
a
divine
right
to
rule
in a
human, hereditary king.
On the other hand, if God
is
king,
then every
human king
is a
usurper. Would
not the
true believer say: "We have
no
other king
but God"?
What
the
Declaration
and the
revolu-
tion it articulated did establish was
political
liberty. So wrote John Marshall
to a
corre-
spondent in his later
years;
in fact, his letter
was
to the
redoubtable Edward Everett,
Unitarian minister. Harvard Professor
of
Greek literature, then
a
U.S. Representa-
tive,
later President
of
Harvard, Governor
of Massachusetts, U.S. Senator from
the
same,
and the man
who shared
the
plat-
form with Lincoln
at
Gettysburg
in
1863.
Wrote Marshall to Everett: "Our resistance
was not made to actual oppression. Ameri-
cans were not pressed down to the earth by
the weight
of
their chains
nor
goaded
to
resistance
by
actual suffering....
The war
was
a war of
principle against
a
system
hostile
to
political liberty, from which op-
pression
was to be
dreaded,
not
against
actual oppression."'
In other words, Americans already knew
political liberty,
or
at least had tasted some
part
of
self-government, through their ex-
perience with the practices and rights,
the
privileges
and
immunities,
of
England's
common law constitution. And they could
see that Parliament and the king were com-
mitted
to a
colonial policy that would
henceforth keep them subordinate.
The
relation
of
mother country
to
dependent
colonies, however appropriate
in
the early
years,
was fast becoming a fiction as a rising
generation
of
Americans learned they had
the wisdom, the skills, the confidence, and
the solidarity
to
govern themselves.
The British ministry understood this
development, too, and when they moved to
foreclose
it, the
colonists struck back.
Be-
cause the Americans soon realized that the
confiict
was
irreversible, they could
not
merely invoke traditional liberties. Besides,
they had learned over the course of
a
decade
of constitutional dispute that their ability
to resist Britain depended
on
their concert
of action,
and
there
was no
established
continent-spanning government
to
whose
traditional authority they could make
ap-
peal. Thus
it is not
quite true,
as
Lincoln
later said, that "the assertion that 'aU men
are created equal' was of no practical use in
effecting
our
separation from Great Brit-
ain"; it was necessary to make intellectually
coherent the appeal
to
traditional
liberties
that would now have
to be
embodied
in
innovative forms—a federal government
that spanned
the
length
of the
Atlantic
coast
and
reconstituted governments
in
"free and independent states."
In asserting
a
right
of
self-government,
the Americans
in
the Declaration appealed
to
a
universal principle, political liberty,
which against the fictions of the time had a
radical meaning, but which they themselves
knew from actual experience, as Marshall's
THE INTERCOLLEGIATE
REVIEW—Fall/Winter2005
Is There a Political Philosophy in the Declaration of Independence?
by James
R,
Stoner
letter makes plain. Even when Lincoln sug-
gests
its
radical potential,
in the
passage
I
quoted above,
he
implicitly clings
to its
specifically political connotation.
The
founders, he adds, "knew the propensity of
prosperity to breed tyrants, and they meant
that when such should reappear in this fair
land
and
commence their vocation, they
should have at least one hard nut to crack."*
At least in the nineteenth and early twenti-
eth centuries, every extension
of
the prin-
ciple of equality in American constitution-
alism—from the extension of the franchise
coupled with
an
attack
on
politically
en-
trenched economic privilege
in
Jacksonian
times,
to the
extension
of
basic economic
and then political rights
to
blacks
and to
women—involved an expansion of the class
who could claim political liberty,
not its
replacement with
a
contrary ideal.
Read
in the
light
of
the document
as a
whole, then,
the
self-evident truths
of
the
Declaration of Independence constitute an
understanding
of
political liberty that
is
the basis
of
our constitutional order. Pre-
cisely because they commit us to liberty on
political questions, they swear
us to no
allegiance
to a
political creed beyond
a
willingness
to
support
the
Constitution.
Because
the
political things
are not the
whole of things, or even the noblest things,
the truths about the political things cannot
pretend
to
capture the whole of
truth:
politi-
cal liberty can be a good, even a noble good,
without being
the
comprehensive good.
But
the
whole truth
is
more complex
than these Aristotelian propositions alone
would indicate. Under
the
theory
of the
Declaration, politics
is
instrumental
in its
origin
and
limited
in its
ends,
but
this
is
precisely what makes it possible for
us
to act
freely in political life,
to
bring truth as we
understand it and goods and interests
as
we
experience them into the public square.
In
other words, political liberty
is
good
be-
cause
it is not the
comprehensive good.
Since human beings are limited beings, we
can only be just
if
we
are also moderate.
Liberalism and Republicanism
It was fashionable
a
couple decades ago
to
debate the revolution and the founding
in
terms
of a
dichotomy between liberalism
and republicanism. Since my foregoing re-
marks might seem
to
align
me
with
the
republican camp, let me clarify the dispute
as
I
understand it and explain where
I
mean
to
be.
On this dichotomy, liberalism describes
a political philosophy, traceable to Hobbes
and Locke, that makes individual rights
fundamental
and
government derivative
and instrumental to their security. Despite
their differences, both Hobbes
and
Locke
thought men equal
in a
pre-political state
of nature, and both thought that equality
was necessarily compromised when society
was formed.
Men are
equally subject
to
government, according
to
Hobbes,
or to
"settled, standing rules," according
to
Locke, but substantial inequalities in prop-
erty
and in all the
other rewards
of
civil
society are allowed—indeed, through com-
merce they would
be
encouraged
to de-
velop.
Hobbes made the sovereign the judge
of what religion would
be
publicly taught
in
the
commonwealth, while Locke
fa-
mously argued that all tolerant sects ought
themselves to be tolerated, but both agreed
that religion could raise no claim to politi-
cal authority.
In
almost
no
other respect
could Hobbes
be
thought
a
champion
of
political liberty. Locke could,
but
political
life was narrowly circumscribed by making
its end the preservation
of
property; there
is a place
for great politics in
Locke,
but only
at
the
moment
of
an "appeal
to
heaven,"
when the people need
to
call their govern-
ment
to
account
for
having changed
its
form illegitimately
or for
having trans-
gressed its end.
THE INTERCOLLEGIATE
REVIEW—Fall/Winter2005
Is There
a
Political Philosophy in the Declaration
of
Independence?
by James
R.
Stoner
The republican alternative
to
liberalism
sketched
by
historians
is
variously attrib-
uted
to
Aristotle, Machiavelli,
and
Harrington, and ought perhaps
to
refer
as
well
to the
early books
of
Montesquieu's
Spirit
of
the Laws
or even to the
Social
Con-
tract
of
Rousseau.
Here, the emphasis is on
selfless devotion
to
the common good, mili-
tary service, education
in
citizenship,
and
the active exercise
of
virtue
in the
public
realm. Property is not ignored, but
it
is the
precondition
of
citizenship:
one
needs
to
own to have the independence to act freely,
and perhaps
one
needs
to own
much
to
know
how to
command.
The
republican
tradition is less philosophical than the lib-
eral,
for the
latter was theoretical
in na-
ture—it was, after
all,
imagining some-
thing new—^while the former generally had
its
eyes
on Rome. While liberalism made its
peace
with human
vices,
such
as
avarice and
ambition, republicanism stressed the dan-
ger of corruption and the need for vigilance
and renewal.
As for
religion, republican-
ism prudently retired
it to a
subordinate
theater
or
boldly made
it
civic, consecrat-
ing
the
republic.
If
the proof texts
of
this
civic republicanism
are
elusive,
its
monu-
ments
are
unmistakable. Most obviously,
they define the architecture of W^ashington,
D.C., and the capitols of many of the states.
In recent years,
the
liberal-republican
dichotomy has been challenged
in
several
ways.
First, scholars such
as
Paul Rahe,
Thomas Pangle,
and
others have argued
that there is
a
distinctively modern repub-
licanism that bridges
the
gap between
the
two schools
of
thought.'
In
Michael
Zuckert's formulation, liberalism dictates
that the end of the polity is the security of
rights,
while republicanism designs
the
political science
by
which
a
government
might
be
constructed to keep rights secure.*
Second, historian Gordon Wood
has ar-
gued that
the
true alternative
to
republi-
canism
is not
liberalism
but
democracy;
republicanism was simply an ideology that
facilitated the transition between two rela-
tively stable,
if
not natural, social and po-
litical regimes, monarchy and democracy.'
The republican founders meant
to
reject
monarchy,
in
which they had been raised,
but they did not intend to establish democ-
racy; despite their intention,
the
changes
they initiated
in
their revolution necessar-
ily entailed democracy, once
men
bred
under monarchy passed from the scene.
While I find some cogency
to
both of the
critiques just outlined,
I do not
think that
they show
the
Declaration
to be
either
staunchly liberal or increasingly democratic
in its implications. Instead,
it
seems
to me
that
the
common
law
constitutionalism
sketched
at the
center
of
the Declaration
defines the form and the limits of political
liberty as
it
was understood by those who
made the revolution and preserves an influ-
ence in the American regime that should be
called Aristotelian.
The
form
of
govern-
ment it supposes has a mixed character; the
goods it
secures
are multiple and not readily
commensurable;
its
adversarial process
invites rhetorical dispute;
its
attitude
to-
ward change is wary, but not dismissive;
it
makes room for equity, without surrender-
ing government by law to rule of the wise.
Common law
is
unwritten law—like that
unwritten "Constitution" mentioned in the
middle of the Declaration—and the friends
of common law would hold with Aristotle
that "[ljaws based
on
unwritten customs
are more sovereign,
and
deal with more
sovereign matters, than written laws."'"
Moreover,
it is
the unwrittenness
of
com-
mon
law and its
consequent openness
to
truth that made possible its concurrence or
coexistence with the Christian religion, and
later with different varieties of that religion
and with Judaism
and
even with other
faiths—and this, without
the
dogmatism
of liberalism's separation
of
church
and
state.
10
THE INTERCOLLEGIATE
REVIEW—Fall/Winter2005
Is There a Political Philosophy in the Declaration of Independence?
by
James
R. Stoner
My point is not to deny classical repub-
lican influences in the American founding
or in the subsequent history of the regime
or especially in its military traditions; nor
to deny that liberalism laid the basis for our
dynamic economy and
its
engine of techno-
logical development and change, nor that
liberalism has influenced the course of our
political development, especially in over-
coming racial slavery. But I think that our
constitutionalism and the spirited political
liberty that gives it shape depend, if they are
to be fully understood historically and ana-
lytically, on other things.
Conclusion
In looking at the Declaration of Indepen-
dence, then, I am saying that we can accept
a few basic political principles that
undergird our constitutional order with-
out having to insist on an orthodoxy of first
principles. We can hold the self-evident
truths to be self-evidently true precisely
because the principles they articulate do
not offer a comprehensive account of hu-
man life. Perhaps no one would disagree if
the issue is put in this way, but it entails, to
my mind, an agreement not to press the
argument of the Declaration beyond its
proper bounds. When the Declaration is
stretched, it becomes a partisan tool, not an
anchor of consensus.
As
there
is
room in the
American polity for one who believes in
rights but not in the Creator who endows us
with them, so there ought to be room for
one who thinks that rights derive from
duties to just such a Creator, or even to a
nature that distinguishes better from worse.
To be true to the spirit of the Declaration
means, from my perspective, not that we
are bound to the most radical reading of its
most abstract truth, but that we ought to
recover the spirited aspiration to self-gov-
ernment that gave the American Revolu-
tion its force and its justification. Rather
than look to an unelected judiciary for the
formulation of our ideals—or to the liberal
philosophers who want to rule through
them—we should neither shy away from
free debate on important social questions
nor demand that every consensus work out
its derivation from first things in order to
count. Let us hold, then, to the principles of
the Declaration as constitutive of our fun-
damental law, but let us not mistake them
as adequate to every exigency in our per-
sonal, our religious, or even our political
lives.
Political philosophy of different sorts
influenced the Declaration, but the Decla-
ration itself
is
not, nor was it meant to be,
a philosophical text. That by its terms it
points us beyond
itself,
to political philoso-
phy and to other
things,
is
no small measure
of its greatness and no little element of its
success.
1.
Poetics,
1451bl ff.
2.
Speech at Springfield, Illinois, June 26, 1857, in
Abraham Lincoln, Selected
Speeches,
Messages,
and
Letters, ed. T. Harry Williams (New
York:
Holt,
Rinehart, and Winston, Inc., 1957), 72-73.
3.
"Letter to Henry Lee," in
Jefferson:
Writings, ed.
Merrill Peterson (New
York:
Library of America,
1984), 1501.
4.
Jefferson, "Notes on the State of Virginia," Query
XVIII, in
Writings,
289. The passage continues: "That
they are not to be violated but with his wrath?"
5.
Letter to Edward Everett, August 2,1826, quoted in
R. Kent Newmyer, John Marshall and the
Heroic
Age
of the Supreme Court (Baton Rouge: Louisiana State
University Press, 2001), 1.
6. Op. dt, 73.
7. Paul Rahe,
Republics
Ancient and Modern (Chapel
Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1992), and
Thomas Pangle, The Spirit of Modern Republicanism
(Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1989).
8. Michael Zuckert, The Natural Rights Republic
(Notre Dame: Notre Dame University Press, 1997).
9. Gordon Wood, The Radicalism of the American
Revolution (New
York:
Knopf,
1993).
10. Aristotle,
Politics
III, 1287bl.
THE
INTERCOLLEGL\TE
REVIEW—Fall/Win
ter
2005
11