UNIVERSITY OF PENNSYLVANIA
JOURNAL OF LAW AND SOCIAL CHANGE
Volume 24, Number 3 2021
323
TRANSGENDER AND GENDER-NONCONFORMING VOTING
RIGHTS AFTER BOSTOCK
BY MICHAEL MILOV-CORDOBA
*
& ALI STACK
**
Abstract. In Bostock v. Clayton County, the Supreme Court issued a landmark holding that allowed
workplace protections for the LGBTQ+ community, including transgender people, to be subsumed
into the Title VII provision prohibiting “sex discrimination. Though Bostock was a Title VII case, the
textualist logic of the majority opinion has important constitutional implications.
In this article, we use Bostock as a point of departure to lay out two novel constitutional theories that
further the voting rights of transgender and gender-nonconforming voters. Under our first theory, we
argue that because Title VII and the Nineteenth Amendment have almost identical language, the
underlying logic of Bostock should govern modern interpretations of the Nineteenth Amendment,
meaning that the Amendment’s protections should extend to transgender and gender-nonconforming
voters. Because the Nineteenth Amendment should be treated as an analogue to the Fifteenth
Amendment, voting regulations that uniquely burden transgender and gender-nonconforming voters
should be regarded as per se unconstitutional under the Nineteenth Amendment. Under our second
theory, we argue that Bostock provides a stepping stone to elevate the standard of review for gender-
based as-applied challenges to voting regulations that implicate gender classifications under the
Fourteenth Amendment from Anderson-Burdick review to intermediate scrutiny.
This article proposes that both theories offer opportunities to better address the barriers posed by the
layering of voter ID laws on top of strict identity document requirements that transgender and gender
non-confirming voters face at the ballot box. To prove this, we conclude by assessing a hypothetical
Nineteenth and Fourteenth Amendment challenge to the joint operation of restrictive voter ID laws
and restrictive identification document requirements as applied to transgender and gender-
nonconforming voters and argue that such regulations should be struck down as violations of both the
Nineteenth Amendment and the Fourteenth Amendment.
* New York University School of Law, J.D., 2021
** UCLA School of Law, J.D. expected 2022. The authors would like to thank Joaquin Gonzalez for his guidance and support
in the initial stages of this project. Thank you also to Jennifer Chacon and Rick Pildes for thoughtful feedback, and to the
University of Pennsylvania Journal of Law and Social Change for careful editing. All errors are our own.
Published by Penn Carey Law: Legal Scholarship Repository, 2021
24 U. PA. J.L. & SOC. CHANGE 4 (2021)
324
INTRODUCTION .................................................................................................................................325
I. THE ROLE OF SEX: BOSTOCK’S IMPLICATIONS FOR THE NINETEENTH
AMENDMENT.........................................................................................................................327
A. On the Meaning of “Sex” ....................................................................................................327
B. Causal Relationship Requirements Under Title VII and the Nineteenth Amendment
..............................................................................................................................................329
II. THE NINETEENTH AMENDMENT’S PROTECTIONS...................................................331
A. The Nineteenth Amendment’s “Thick Commitment to Equality .............................332
B. The Nineteenth Amendment’s Scrutiny Framework: Per Se Unconstitutionality.....335
C. Triggers for Nineteenth Amendment Protections ..........................................................337
III. BOSTOCK’S IMPLICATIONS ON THE FOURTEENTH AMENDMENT ...................339
IV. ASSESSING A POTENTIAL NINETEENTH AMENDMENT CHALLENGE:
VOTER ID .................................................................................................................................343
CONCLUSION .......................................................................................................................................349
https://scholarship.law.upenn.edu/jlasc/vol24/iss3/2
TRANSGENDER AND GENDER-NONCONFORMING VOTING RIGHTS AFTER BOSTOCK
325
INTRODUCTION
Last June, the Supreme Court issued a landmark holding that allowed workplace protections
for the LGBTQ+ community, including transgender people, to be subsumed into Title VII’s provision
prohibiting “sex discrimination. In his majority opinion, Justice Gorsuch held that sex, which the
Court defined as “the biological distinctions between male and female,”
1
plays a “necessary and
undisguisable role”
2
in an employment decision that turns on a person’s gay or transgender identity. In
so holding, the Bostock Court provided a textualist justification for a more expansive scope of workplace
protections afforded on the basis of sex.
Though Bostock was a Title VII case, the textualist logic of the majority opinion implicates
other civil rights and has important constitutional implications. For example, civil rights litigators are
seeking to leverage the underlying logic of Bostock to further the civil rights of incarcerated transgender
individuals,
3
and Fourteenth Amendment Equal Protection analysis is already shifting in line with the
Court’s post-Bostock understanding of sex and gender identity.
4
This article seeks to further the voting rights of transgender and gender-nonconforming
voters by assessing the implications of Bostock on Nineteenth Amendment and Fourteenth Amendment
voting rights jurisprudence. Regarding the former, the nearly identical language of the Nineteenth
Amendment to the Title VII sex discrimination provision suggests that a similar textual reading of the
Nineteenth Amendment can serve to protect the voting rights of transgender and gender-
nonconforming individuals. Regarding the latter, the Bostock Court’s recognition that discrimination on
the basis of sex necessarily contains discrimination on the basis of gender identity provides a foothold
to broaden Fourteenth Amendment voting rights jurisprudence. Specifically, this article proposes that
both theories offer opportunities to better address the barriers posed by the layering of voter ID laws
on top of the strict identity document requirements that transgender and gender-nonconforming voters
face at the ballot box.
5
In this article, we use Bostock as a point of departure to lay out two novel constitutional theories
that further the voting rights of transgender and gender-nonconforming voters. Under our first theory,
we argue that because Title VII and the Nineteenth Amendment have almost identical language, the
logic of Bostock should govern analyses of the Nineteenth Amendment. Under this reading, “[t]he right
of citizens of the United States to vote shall not be denied or abridged by the United States or by any
State on account of [gender identity],”
6
meaning that the Amendment’s protections should extend to
transgender and gender-nonconforming voters. Because the Nineteenth Amendment should be treated
as an analogue to the Fifteenth Amendment, voting regulations that uniquely burden transgender and
gender-nonconforming voters should be regarded as “per se unconstitutional.”
7
1
Bostock v. Clayton Cnty., 140 S. Ct. 1731, 1737, 1739 (2020).
2
Id. at 1737.
3
See infra Part III.
4
As laid out in Part III, Courts have already begun to operationalize the Bostock Court’s logic to afford transgender
individuals the gender protections inherent in the Equal Protection Clause. See infra note 106–07 and accompanying text.
5
See infra Part IV.
6
See infra Part II.
7
See Jones v. Governor of Fla., 975 F.3d 1016, 1043 (11th Cir. 2020) (“But the [Fifteenth] [A]mendment established a
powerful baseline: States must set voter qualifications without any regard to race. The Fifteenth Amendment does not subject
race-based voter qualifications to strict scrutiny—they are per se unconstitutional. . . . The Nineteenth Amendment forbids the
Published by Penn Carey Law: Legal Scholarship Repository, 2021
24 U. PA. J.L. & SOC. CHANGE 4 (2021)
326
One all too common example of such regulations, assessed in detail in Part IV, is the
enforcement of voter ID laws that require voters to show an identification card with a gender marker
in order to vote or cast a provisional ballot. Operating in tandem with laws that require voters to
undergo significant expenses to obtain an acceptable form of ID that matches their gender identity,
8
these strict voter ID regimes necessarily implicate a gender classification between cisgender voters and
transgender and gender-nonconforming voters, uniquely burdening the latter. Accordingly, such
schemes should be regarded as unconstitutional under the Nineteenth Amendment, at least as applied
to transgender and gender-nonconforming voters, and be struck down.
9
Under our second theory, we argue that Bostock has provided a stepping stone to elevate the
standard of review for gender-based, as-applied challenges to voter ID laws under the Fourteenth
Amendment. After the Bostock Court’s recognition that sex classifications operate not merely on a
male/female sex binary but across a diverse range of gender identities, classifications that sort and
burden voters on the basis of cisgender and transgender identity, as the combination of voter ID and
strict identity document laws do, are more appropriately reviewed under intermediate scrutiny rather
than under Anderson-Burdick review, which courts typically use to review generally applicable election
laws, including voter ID laws.
10
This article proceeds in four parts. The first section makes the case that the textualist logic of
Bostock should apply to the Nineteenth Amendment and, for that reason, the same group of individuals
protected under Title VII’s prohibition against discrimination on the basis of sex should be protected
under the Nineteenth Amendment—namely, that transgender and gender-nonconforming voters
should also be protected under the Nineteenth Amendment. With clarity about who is protected under
the Nineteenth Amendment, the second section examines what protections are afforded to voters
under the Nineteenth Amendment. Here we argue that for textual and jurisprudential reasons, gender
classifications in the voting context that disproportionately burden voters on one side of the
classification should be treated like comparable racial classifications in the voting context and be
regarded as per se unconstitutional. In the third section we argue that election laws that implicate gender
classifications challenged under the Fourteenth Amendment should at least receive intermediate
scrutiny, rather than Anderson-Burdick review. Finally, in the last section we assess a hypothetical
Nineteenth and Fourteenth Amendment challenge to the joint operation of restrictive voter ID laws
and restrictive identification document requirements as applied to transgender and gender-
nonconforming voters. We argue that such a scheme should be struck down under our framework.
use of sex as a voter qualification in the same way.”); infra Part II.
8
See, e.g., ALA. CODE § 22-9A-19 (2019) (requiring a court order certifying that a person’s sex has been changed via a
surgical procedure in order to issue an amended birth certificate). A petition for a name and gender marker change in Alabama
costs roughly $100, which does not include fees for new identity documents or the gender confirmation surgery required by the
state. Alabama, CAMPAIGN FOR S. EQUALITY: LEGAL RESOURCES (2021), https://southernequality.org/legal-
resources/alabama [https://perma.cc/7Q6D-R8K6] (last visited June 30, 2021).
9
See infra Part IV. Prior to Bostock, Richard Hasen and Leah Litman had mounted a powerful argument to interpret
Congress’ enforcement powers under the Nineteenth Amendment to include legislation that targets election policies that
disproportionately burden transgender and gender-nonconforming voters, such as voter ID laws. See Richard L. Hasen & Leah
M. Litman, Thin and Thick Conceptions of the Nineteenth Amendment Right to Vote and Congress’s Power to Enforce It, 108 GEO. L.J. 27,
69–70 (2020). Our article builds upon their important work but focuses on potential constitutional challenges to such laws after
Bostock, rather than on Congress enforcement powers under the Nineteenth Amendment.
10
See infra Part III.
https://scholarship.law.upenn.edu/jlasc/vol24/iss3/2
TRANSGENDER AND GENDER-NONCONFORMING VOTING RIGHTS AFTER BOSTOCK
327
I. THE ROLE OF SEX: BOSTOCK’S IMPLICATIONS FOR THE NINETEENTH
AMENDMENT
This section argues that the textualist logic of Bostock should apply to the Nineteenth
Amendment and, accordingly, that the same scope of individuals protected under Title VII should also
be protected under the Nineteenth Amendment in the voting context. Because the Bostock Court
clarified that transgender individuals are protected from discrimination in employment under Title VII,
the Nineteenth Amendment can and should be read to encompass the voting rights of transgender and
gender-nonconforming voters.
A. On the Meaning of “Sex”
In Bostock, the Supreme Court held that discrimination against transgender and gay individuals
fundamentally and inextricably turns on notions of “sex.” While sex was not the sole cause of
discrimination in any of the consolidated cases before the Court, the Court found that “it is impossible
to discriminate against a person for being . . . transgender without discriminating against that individual
based on sex.”
11
To argue for a transposition of this argument onto the Nineteenth Amendment, we
explore the Bostock Court’s treatment of the meaning of sex and the causal language in Title VII.
The Bostock Court’s textualist focus allows us to draw clear parallels between Title VII and the
Nineteenth Amendment. First, consider parallel language in the Title VII provision and the Nineteenth
Amendment. The Nineteenth Amendment states: “The right of citizens of the United States to vote
shall not be denied or abridged by the United States or by any State on account of sex.”
12
The language
used in the Title VII provision with respect to sex is nearly identical—discrimination in hiring, firing,
and employment opportunities “because of [an] individual’s . . . sex” is prohibited.
13
On a textualist
account, it is reasonable to infer from the nearly identical phrasing of these texts that those protected
under Title VII’s prohibition against sex discrimination would also receive the protections of the
Nineteenth Amendment.
Indeed, in his lengthy originalist dissent, Justice Alito confirms this theory. According to
Justice Alito, where the text of both a statutory and constitutional provision are substantively
indistinguishable, so too is the meaning of the text.
14
Applying this theory to Title VII, he specifically
notes that the language in the Nineteenth Amendment is “substantively indistinguishable” from that of
Title VII.
15
Justice Alito’s interpretive position is consistent with other Supreme Court precedent, where
the Court has found that unless evidence of contrary intent is present in the text of a statute or the
Constitution, it is appropriate to read the same meaning into substantively identical language.
16
All of
11
Bostock v. Clayton Cty., 140 S. Ct. 1731, 1741 (2020).
12
U.S. CONST. amend. XIX, § 1.
13
Civil Rights Act of 1964, 42 U.S.C. § 2000e-2(a)(1).
14
Bostock, 140 S. Ct. at 1768 (Alito, J., dissenting) (“Long before Title VII was adopted, many pioneering state and
federal laws [including the Nineteenth Amendment] had used language substantively indistinguishable from Title VII’s critical
phrase, ‘discrimination because of sex.’”).
15
Id.
16
See, e.g., General Elec. Co. v. Gilbert, 429 U.S. 125, 133 (1976) (regarding prior constitutional interpretations of the
Equal Protection Clause’s prohibition on sex discrimination as “a useful starting point” to interpret Title VII’s prohibition on
sex discrimination due to textual “similarities”); Patton v. United States, 281 U.S. 276, 301 (1930) (holding that where language
Published by Penn Carey Law: Legal Scholarship Repository, 2021
24 U. PA. J.L. & SOC. CHANGE 4 (2021)
328
this lends support to the argument that the Bostock Court’s holding clarifies the scope of voters
protected under the Nineteenth Amendment.
Second, consider the ways in which Bostock jettisoned the intent of the drafters from the
statute’s plain meaning. The Court does not entertain at length the scope of the term “sex as it was
understood at the time of passage of the Civil Rights Act of 1964.
17
It adopts the narrowest
interpretation of the meaning of “sex offered by the parties—”biological distinctions between male
and female”—and notes that its holding does not turn on what the drafters meant by the word, but
rather on the fact that discrimination on the basis of sexual orientation or gender identity necessarily
first requires sex-based discrimination.
18
Even assuming the premise that the drafters of the Civil Rights
Act did not intend to capture issues of gender identity or sexual orientation explicitly in the language
of the provision, the Court was, through its singular focus on the text, nonetheless able to reach the
conclusion that the provision protects transgender individuals.
19
The same logic should apply to the
Nineteenth Amendment.
An originalist position, such as that offered by Justice Alito in his dissent, may argue that
contrary intent can be inferred from the genesis of the Nineteenth Amendment as the direct result of
a women’s suffrage movement that sought the “equal treatment of men and women” and not of all
homosexual, transgender, or gender-nonconforming individuals. On this basis, an originalist may argue
that the framers of the Nineteenth Amendment could not have meant anything beyond sex as the
biological differences between male and female, and thus the Court’s reading of Title VII should not
be read into the Nineteenth Amendment. But this position returns to an immaterial debate about the
meaning of “sex as a basis for this assertion.
20
Again, the Bostock Court did not dispute the meaning
of “sex at the time of enactment of Title VII.
21
Courts should similarly not dispute its meaning in
1924.
But even if, in the case of a Nineteenth Amendment challenge, a court feels obliged to look
to the plain meaning of sex at the time of the Amendment’s enactment, this would in turn reveal an
even more robust definition of sex than the meaning of “sex at the time of the passage of the Civil
Rights Act that makes a stronger case for inclusion of transgender and gender-nonconforming
individuals. Though there is little jurisprudential analysis of the word “sex from the early twentieth
century when the Nineteenth Amendment was enacted, the colloquial and even scholarly meaning of
“sex began to evolve around the turn of the century as scientists began to identify the biological bases
of sex characteristics.
22
Scientists and scholars began to recognize that biological sex distinctions were
separate from social constructions,
23
though sex continued to signify a bundle of “traits, attitudes, and
in a federal statute mirrored that of Article III of the Constitution, “it is fair to assume that the framers of the statute . . . intended
they have the same meaning . . . “); Baldwin v. Franks, 120 U.S. 678, 692 (1887) (holding that the meaning of the word “citizen”
was the same in a federal statute and in the Fourteenth Amendment of the Constitution, given that there was “nothing to indicate
that any[one] other than a citizen [as the meaning of the word in the Fourteenth Amendment] was meant . . .”).
17
Bostock, 140 S. Ct. at 1739.
18
Id. at 1739.
19
Id. at 1754.
20
Id. at 1772 (Alito, J., dissenting).
21
Id. at 1739.
22
Jillian Todd Weiss, Transgender Identity, Textualism, and the Supreme Court: What Is the “Plain Meaning” of “Sex in Title VII
of the Civil Rights Act of 1964?, 18 TEMP. POL. & C.R. L. REV. 573, 599 (2009).
23
Id. at 602.
https://scholarship.law.upenn.edu/jlasc/vol24/iss3/2
TRANSGENDER AND GENDER-NONCONFORMING VOTING RIGHTS AFTER BOSTOCK
329
behaviors until the later twentieth century when sex was uncoupled from gender.
24
It would seem,
then, that even early twentieth century conceptions of sex necessarily involved gendered traits, attitudes,
and behaviors. Thus even if a court were to find that the drafters of the Nineteenth Amendment did
not intend its protections to specifically include transgender people,
25
this meaning of “sex broadens
the possible scope of a first but-for cause of discriminatory treatment in voting that would form the
basis of a Nineteenth Amendment violation, following Bostock. Though few in 1920 might have
expected the specific result of expanding Nineteenth Amendment protections to transgender people,
it would be incorrect to deny that such a result follows from the text.
26
B. Causal Relationship Requirements Under Title VII and the Nineteenth Amendment
Title VII and the Nineteenth Amendment additionally share important causal language that is
central to the Bostock Court’s holding and thus central to our argument here. Title VII prohibits
discrimination “because of sex,
27
and the Nineteenth Amendment prohibits the abridgment or denial
of the right to vote “on account of sex.”
28
The Court has held that the ordinary meaning of “because
of is identical to the “on account of phrasing used in the Nineteenth Amendment.
29
Moreover,
neither Title VII nor the Nineteenth Amendment include “solely” or “primarily because of in their
phrasing. In the context of Title VII, the Bostock Court determined that such an omission evinces
Congress’s interest in preserving the possibility of more than one but-for cause of discrimination.
30
Similarly, the drafters of the Nineteenth Amendment did not syntactically prohibit a second but-for
cause of the denial or abridgement of the right to vote, over and above “sex.”
31
This observation is
integral to mirroring the Bostock Court’s interpretation of Title VII that we believe clarifies the broad
scope of protections under the Nineteenth Amendment.
The Bostock Court built on the above textual interpretations to hold that in the case of an
employer discriminating against a transgender employee, two causal factors are involved: first, the
person’s sex assigned at birth (thereby satisfying the Title VII requirement) and second, the sex with
which that individual identifies.
32
The Court further explained that when an employer fires a woman
assigned male at birth but retains a woman assigned female at birth, the employer discriminates against
the transgender woman for “traits or actions that the employer tolerates from a cisgender woman.
33
24
Id. at 603.
25
It is possible, though, that a court would not reach this extratextual consideration of the historical meaning of “sex.”
The Bostock Court found the word to carry a plain meaning, and a court may find the same of the Nineteenth Amendment. See
Bostock v. Clayton Cnty., 140 S. Ct. 1731, 1739 (2020).
26
See id.
27
Civil Rights Act of 1964, 42 U. S. C. § 2000e-2(a)(1).
28
U.S. CONST. amend. XIX, § 1.
29
See Univ. of Tex. Sw. Med. Ctr. v. Nassar, 570 U. S. 338, 350 (2013) (affirming precedent construing “because of”
the same way as “on account of”).
30
Bostock v. Clayton Cty., 140 S. Ct. 1731, 1739 (2020).
31
U.S. CONST. amend. XIX, § 1.
32
Bostock, 140 S. Ct. at 1742. We note here that while “identification” with a sex is the language the Court employs to
refer to a transgender or gender-nonconforming person’s gender, we recognize that phrases like “identifies with are often used
to undermine and detract from a person’s true gender.
33
Id. at 1737.
Published by Penn Carey Law: Legal Scholarship Repository, 2021
24 U. PA. J.L. & SOC. CHANGE 4 (2021)
330
For the purposes of Title VII, then, an employer is in violation of the law as soon as sex is considered
at all, even if the discrimination does not stop at the employee’s sex or perceived sex. The Court
analogizes this situation to an employer who has a policy of firing any woman discovered to be a
Yankees fan—that firing is “because of sex” if the employer retains men who are Yankees fans.
34
In
each of these examples, sex-based rules result in discrimination.
35
An employer’s insistence on a different but-for cause of discrimination is immaterial. First,
the Court notes that it is not possible to understand transgender status without invoking the definition
of sex as presented above.
36
Necessarily, then, a decision to hire or fire a transgender individual is, in
part, because of that person’s sex.
37
The Court further discounts “conversational” answers to reasons
for firing as notable or controlling—though colloquially, an employer may say that a person was fired
for being transgender and not because of sex, the Court holds that the statute’s strict terms, as
interpreted to allow multiple but-for causes, reign.
38
Even Justice Alito conceded that, in 1964, Congress did not require plaintiffs to show that a
Title VII-protected category was the sole cause of the discrimination.
39
In light of this concession,
Justice Alito’s main position still holds true in light of the majority opinion: “[i]f ‘sex in Title VII means
biologically male or female, then discrimination because of sex means discrimination because the
person in question is biologically male or biologically female . . . .”
40
Indeed, the discrimination occurs
not solely “because that person is sexually attracted to members of the same sex or identifies as a
member of a particular gender, as Justice Alito squarely rejects, but in addition to discrimination based
on a person’s perceived or actual sex assigned at birth. The application of the Bostock holding to the
Nineteenth Amendment mirrors this logic: an unconstitutional classification that burdens only
transgender and gender-nonconforming individuals—such as that presented in Part IV of this article
is necessarily a sex-based classification under the Bostock Court’s clarification of the scope of sex-based
discrimination.
Fearing the slippery slope of the majority’s logic, Justice Alito raises a concern about the
Court’s distinction between those characteristics that are “inextricably” related to sex and those which
are only tangentially related to the concept of sex.
41
Specifically, Justice Alito asks whether
discrimination based on words modified by the adjective “sexual” would be violative of Title VII, and
he presents a hypothetical about an employer discriminating on the basis of a person’s history of sexual
harassment.
42
Such a question is an oversimplification of the Court’s position that certain categories
34
Id. at 1742.
35
Previous Title VII jurisprudence supports this textualist read of the statutory language. In Oncale v. Sundowner Offshore
Servs., 523 U.S. 75, 80 (1998), the Court held that workplace sexual harassment, regardless of the sex of the harasser and the
person harassed, constitutes “discrimination. . . . because of. . . . sex, as the relevant inquiry is whether members of one sex are
exposed to disadvantageous terms or conditions of employment to which members of the other sex are not exposed.
36
Bostock, 140 S. Ct. at 1742.
37
Id.
38
Id. at 1745.
39
Id. at 1757 (Alito, J., dissenting).
40
Id.
41
Id. at 1761 (Alito, J., dissenting).
42
Id.
https://scholarship.law.upenn.edu/jlasc/vol24/iss3/2
TRANSGENDER AND GENDER-NONCONFORMING VOTING RIGHTS AFTER BOSTOCK
331
like motherhood, as was the case in Phillips v. Martin Marietta Corporation
43
—clearly depend on sex, while
others do not.
44
Justice Alito obtusely ignores the fact that “sex here is a polyseme—that which
concerns sexual relations and activity is distinct, in the context of the Court’s opinion, from
characteristics that turn on biological sex. But more importantly, Justice Alito’s concern is simply
irrelevant in the voting context. No voting process or mechanism invokes anything tenuously sexual
beyond that which is inextricably linked to sex. A voter’s registration, identification requirements,
polling place, and voting history only bear on a small subset of protected characteristics, not a person’s
history of “sexual intercourse or interest in “sexual content,” for example, as Justice Alito offers.
45
Put
simply, applied to the Nineteenth Amendment, Justice Alito’s concern about overprotection is
inapposite.
Accordingly, as a result of the textual parallels between Title VII and the Nineteenth
Amendment, it is possible to read these same conclusions into the voting context. An abridgement or
denial of the right to vote because of, but not limited to, sex would therefore be a constitutional
violation. Yet because it is not possible to deny or abridge the right to vote of a transgender person
because of their gender identity without invoking the “bundle of traits, attitudes, and behaviors
attributed to sex, this abridgement or denial should receive constitutional protections under the
Nineteenth Amendment.
II. THE NINETEENTH AMENDMENT’S PROTECTIONS
In offering a textual justification for a capacious understanding of discrimination on the basis
of sex under Title VII, we believe Bostock necessarily clarified the scope of individuals protected by the
Nineteenth Amendment. If that is the case, then the precise content of the protections of the
Nineteenth Amendment have become more relevant. This section discerns those protections by
examining the history of Nineteenth Amendment challenges, as well as recent Nineteenth Amendment
scholarship.
We argue that the little Nineteenth Amendment case law that we have, the text and history of
the Amendment, and existing scholarship on the Amendment all point toward what some scholars have
termed a “thick conception of the Nineteenth Amendment, understood as a binding commitment to
the ideals of political equality in voting and equal access to the political process regardless of one’s sex.
46
Although the depth of this commitment is yet to manifest in the Court’s underdeveloped Nineteenth
Amendment jurisprudence,
47
Fifteenth Amendment jurisprudence provides an analogous body of law
43
Phillips v. Martin Marietta Corp., 400 U.S. 542 (1971).
44
Though we highlight the Court’s position on motherhood here to distinguish between those characteristics that
necessarily depend on sex and those that do not, we acknowledge a diverse conception of parenthood that
includes transgender and gender-nonconforming parents.
45
Bostock, 140 S. Ct. at 1761 (Alito, J., dissenting).
46
See Hasen & Litman, supra note 7, at 33 (defending a thick conception of the Nineteenth Amendment and defining
it as “protect[ing] against the perpetuation of political-power disparities on the basis of gender” and “protect[ing] against the
subordination of women in U.S. politics”); see also Paula A. Monopoli, The Constitutional Development of the Nineteenth Amendment in
the Decade Following Ratification, 11 CONLAWNOW 61 (2019) (contrasting thick and thin conceptions of the Nineteenth
Amendment).
47
See Steve Kolbert, The Nineteenth Amendment Enforcement Power (but First, Which One Is the Nineteenth Amendment, Again?,
43 FLA. ST. U. L. REV. 507, 509–10 (2016) (“Despite the Nineteenth Amendment’s existence for nearly a century and the recent
popular and scholarly attention to voting rights, the Nineteenth Amendment has not received any serious treatment or
Published by Penn Carey Law: Legal Scholarship Repository, 2021
24 U. PA. J.L. & SOC. CHANGE 4 (2021)
332
on which to base renewed Nineteenth Amendment jurisprudence that aligns a court’s scrutiny of
regulations implicating gender classifications in voting with this “thick conception of the Amendment.
As with voting regulations that set voter qualifications in any part on the basis of race, voting regulations
that do comparable things with respect to gender identity should automatically be treated as per se
unconstitutional, as they are under the Fifteenth Amendment. We believe our proposed framework is
consistent with the text, purpose, and demands of the Nineteenth Amendment, and, as we show in
Part IV, would offer voting rights litigators a new tool for challenging voter ID laws that
disproportionately burden trans and gender-nonconforming voters.
A. The Nineteenth Amendment’s “Thick Commitment to Equality
Since its passage in 1920,
48
federal courts have had few occasions to specify the protections
afforded to voters by the Nineteenth Amendment. The Nineteenth Amendment’s Enforcement Clause,
for example, has never been interpreted by the Supreme Court.
49
Indeed, scholars have explicitly noted
the dearth of case law and scholarship on the Nineteenth Amendment.
50
To this day, the Supreme Court has heard only two Nineteenth Amendment challenges: Leser
v. Garnett in 1922 and Breedlove v. Shuttles in 1937. Both provide little insight into the Amendment’s
substantive content because the Court provides little analysis of the Amendment, and the cases precede
the Court’s adoption of its modern voting rights jurisprudence. In Leser v. Garnett, the Court’s first foray
into Nineteenth Amendment jurisprudence, the Court merely affirmed that the protections of the
Nineteenth Amendment applied automatically after its ratification.
51
Fifteen years later, in Breedlove v.
Suttles, the court upheld a Georgia regulation that exempted women who did not register to vote from
paying a poll tax against a Nineteenth Amendment challenge.
52
In doing so, the Court offered only a single paragraph of analysis on the Nineteenth
Amendment. In this paragraph, the Court held that the Nineteenth Amendment does not place
restrictions on a state’s ability to levy or collect taxes and concluded that “[i]t is fanciful to suggest that
the Georgia law is a mere disguise under which to deny or abridge the right of men to vote on account
consideration as a tool to protect voting rights.”).
48
For an analysis of the legislative history leading up to the passage of the Nineteenth Amendment, see Kolbert, supra
note 49, at 534–40.
49
See Eric S. Fish, Note, The Twenty-Sixth Amendment Enforcement Power, 121 YALE L.J. 1168, 1178–79 (2012).
50
See, e.g., Hasen & Litman, supra note 7, at 33 (“Given the paucity of judicial interpretations and scholarly writings on
the scope of the Nineteenth Amendment, even one hundred years after its ratification, we believe that its interpretation remains
up for grabs in important respects.”); Kolbert, supra note 45, at 508–09. (“Yet, no legislation and barely any litigation have arisen
as a result of the Nineteenth Amendment. One legal encyclopedia spends a mere sixty-nine words on the Nineteenth
Amendment. . . . The Nineteenth Amendment receives so little attention, scholars joke about it.”) (footnote omitted). That said,
the 100
th
anniversary of the Nineteenth Amendment has occasioned a recent resurgence of scholarship. For example, last winter
the Yale Law Journal hosted a symposium on the Nineteenth Amendment, featuring three articles. See Symposium, The Nineteenth
Amendment at 100, 129 YALE L.J. 450 (2020), https://www.yalelawjournal.org/collection/nineteenth-amendment-at-100
[https://perma.cc/WXR8-5LPJ] (last visited June 30, 2021).
51
See Leser v. Garnett, 258 U.S. 130 (1922) (striking down a provision of Maryland’s Constitution limiting the franchise
to men but providing minimal analysis of the substance of the Amendment itself).
52
See Breedlove v. Suttles, 302 U.S. 277 (1937).
https://scholarship.law.upenn.edu/jlasc/vol24/iss3/2
TRANSGENDER AND GENDER-NONCONFORMING VOTING RIGHTS AFTER BOSTOCK
333
of their sex.”
53
By sanctioning a voting regulation containing an explicit gender-based classification, in
its only word on the substantive protections of the Nineteenth Amendment, the Court appeared to put
forward what some scholars have called a “thin” conception of the protections afforded by the
Nineteenth Amendment: because Breedlove “allowed for de jure gender discrimination in voting rules,”
Richard Hasen and Leah Litman argue in a recent article on the Nineteenth Amendment, “[t]he case
offers the thinnest possible version of the Nineteenth Amendment.”
54
Yet one can also read Breedlove’s understanding of the Nineteenth Amendment in a more
expansive light. Although the Court declined to strike down the gender classification, it also recognized
that the Nineteenth Amendment “applies to men and women alike.”
55
In this way, “the Nineteenth
Amendment [was] understood [by the Court] to extend beyond [its] paradigmatic protected classes,”
56
suggesting a more robust conception of the Nineteenth Amendment than Breedlove’s holding might
indicate.
Although Breedlove is the Supreme Court’s one and only real assessment of a Nineteenth
Amendment challenge, as other scholars have noted, one can glean the outline of a “thicker”
57
conception of the Nineteenth Amendment in Supreme Court dicta in voting rights and non-voting
rights cases. For some scholars, the seed of such a conception is found, ironically, in Adkins v. Children’s
Hospital.
58
In this case, the Court struck down a minimum wage law for women and children as a
violation of the Due Process Clause.
59
Yet in his majority opinion, Justice Sutherland briefly opined on
the significance of the Nineteenth Amendment, which had passed just a few years earlier:
But the ancient inequality of the sexes, otherwise than physical, as suggested in the
Muller case has continued “with diminishing intensity.” In view of the great—not to
say revolutionary—changes which have taken place since that utterance, in the
contractual, political, and civil status of women, culminating in the Nineteenth
Amendment, it is not unreasonable to say that these differences have now come
almost, if not quite, to the vanishing point.
60
While the holding—and much of the language—of Adkins itself remains a paternalistic relic
of another era, scholars have interpreted this passage as an affirmation by the Court that the ratification
of the Nineteenth Amendment committed the country to the ideal of robust political sex equality.
According to Reva Siegel, for example, by “discussing equality for women in the framework of the
suffrage debates[,] as emancipation from the traditions of reasoning about gender embodied in the
common law of marital status, Adkins “approached the Nineteenth Amendment as embodying a sex
53
Id. at 284.
54
See Hasen & Litman, supra note 7, at 27, 32, 34.
55
Breedlove v. Suttles, 302 U.S. 277, 283 (1937).
56
See Fish, supra note 48, at 1175.
57
See Monopoli, supra note 43, at 66.
58
See Reva B. Siegel, She the People: The Nineteenth Amendment, Sex Equality, Federalism, and the Family, 115 HARV. L. REV.
947, 1013–17 (2002).
59
See Adkins v. Children’s Hospital, 261 U.S. 525, 553 (1923) (striking down a D.C. minimum wage law as a violation
of the Due Process Clause).
60
See id. (quoting Muller v. Oregon, 208 U.S. 412 (1908)).
Published by Penn Carey Law: Legal Scholarship Repository, 2021
24 U. PA. J.L. & SOC. CHANGE 4 (2021)
334
equality norm that had implications for constitutional questions other than voting.”
61
In other words
the Amendment contains constitutional protections beyond the enfranchisement of women.
As other scholars have noted,
62
the Court has occasionally drawn upon this thicker,
emancipatory conception of the substantive protections of the Nineteenth Amendment. In Reynolds v.
Sims, where the Court first applied one-person, one-vote to strike down a malapportioned districting
plan, Justice Douglas characterized the Nineteenth Amendment, in passing, as part of a project of
“political equality”
63
—a far cry from Justice Brandeis’ implicit sanctioning of gender classifications in
the voting context in Breedlove.
64
Along similar lines, in a footnote to her Shelby County v. Holder dissent,
Justice Ginsburg offered an intratextual reading of the Nineteenth Amendment, as embodying, along
with the Fifteenth and Twenty-Sixth Amendments, a commitment “to mak[e] the right to vote equally
real for all U.S. citizens.”
65
Although state courts were the primary locus for Nineteenth Amendment litigation shortly
after the Amendment’s passage, the cases provide little insight as to how a modern court should apply
the Amendment, as most of these cases were decided in the early twentieth century and involved
challenges to facial bars to women’s right to vote. Yet even in these older cases, state appellate courts
drew upon this thicker conception of Nineteenth Amendment protections. For example, in Graves v.
Eubank, decided just two years prior to Adkins and one year after the Amendment’s ratification, the
Alabama Supreme Court held that Alabama’s poll tax requirement extended to women. But in addition
to offering this “thin” formal holding, the court went further, claiming that the Amendment
“automatically strikes from the state laws, organic and statutory, all discriminatory features authorizing
one sex to vote and excluding the other, or placing conditions or burdens upon one not placed upon the other as a
condition precedent to the right to vote. . . .”
66
Such language suggests something more robust than simple
formal equality and certainly something far more protective than the paternalistic notion of the
Nineteenth Amendment at work in Breedlove.
67
61
See Siegel, supra note 58, at 1013.
62
See Hasen & Litman, supra note 7, at 28–31.
63
See Reynolds v. Sims, 377 U.S. 533, 558 (1964) (“And, finally, we concluded [in Gray v. Sanders]: ‘The conception of
political equality from the Declaration of Independence, to Lincoln’s Gettysburg Address, to the Fifteenth, Seventeenth, and
Nineteenth Amendments can mean only one thing—one person, one vote.’”) (quoting Gray v. Sanders, 372 U.S. 368, 381 (1963)).
64
On the sexism in Breedlove, see Hasen & Litman, supra note 7, at 38 (“Breedlove’s embrace of sexism, its reliance of
[sic] the repudiated Muller case, and its decision to ignore Adkins more progressive view of the Nineteenth Amendment, moved
the issue of women’s voting rights and the scope of the Amendment backwards.”).
65
See Shelby County v. Holder, 570 U.S. 529, 567 n.2 (2013) (J., Ginsburg, dissenting). See also Hasen & Litman, supra
note 7, at 31 (describing Justice Ginsburg’s dissent as embodying a thick conception of the Fifteenth Amendment, and thus, by
implication, of the Nineteenth Amendment).
66
See Graves v. Eubank, 205 Ala. 174, 175 (1921) (emphasis added).
67
Beyond the few cases that constitute our Nineteenth Amendment Supreme Court jurisprudence, the text and history
of the Amendment also point toward a thicker conception. See Hasen & Litman, supra note 7, at 38–56 (defending a thick
conception of the Nineteenth Amendment on the basis of the Amendment’s text and history, the broader constitutional history
of the expansion of voting rights, and the Court’s recognition of voting as a fundamental right); Siegel, supra note 58, at 952
(“This Article proposes a synthetic reading of the Fourteenth and Nineteenth Amendments that would bring to the interpretation
of the Equal Protection Clause a knowledge of the family-based status order through which women were disfranchised for most
of this nation’s history and from which they were emancipated after over a half century of struggle. Interpreted from this
sociohistoric standpoint, a core meaning of equal protection for women is freedom from historic forms of subordination in the
family.”).
https://scholarship.law.upenn.edu/jlasc/vol24/iss3/2
TRANSGENDER AND GENDER-NONCONFORMING VOTING RIGHTS AFTER BOSTOCK
335
B. The Nineteenth Amendment’s Scrutiny Framework: Per Se Unconstitutionality
Assuming the ratification of the Nineteenth Amendment committed the country to a “thick,”
robust ideal of political equality, what sort of scrutiny framework should a modern court apply when
assessing Nineteenth Amendment challenges?
We begin with what courts have done already. On the one hand, courts sometimes have read
Nineteenth Amendments protections as simply coextensive with the Fourteenth Amendment. In Ball
v. Brown, for example, a federal district court explicitly adopted this theory, noting that “[t]o the extent
that the Nineteenth Amendment provides a further guarantee of the right to vote, that guarantee is
encompassed within the [F]ourteenth [A]mendment guarantee of equal protection under laws
prohibiting state action which invidiously encroaches upon the right to vote.”
68
Under current
Fourteenth Amendment jurisprudence, gender classifications receive intermediate scrutiny, requiring
the government to show that the challenged law furthers an important government interest and uses
means substantially related to that interest.
69
By extension, according to the logic of the Ball v. Brown
court, Nineteenth Amendment challenges to voting regulations implicating gender classifications
should similarly receive intermediate scrutiny.
On the other hand, other courts have adopted the theory that the Nineteenth Amendment
embodies analogous protections to those of the Fifteenth Amendment. The Supreme Court appeared
to adopt such a theory in Leser v. Grant, noting that the Nineteenth Amendment “is in character and
phraseology precisely similar to the Fifteenth.”
70
Similarly, shortly after the Nineteenth Amendment’s
passage, a state high court held that “[t]he privileges conferred upon women by the Nineteenth
Amendment are precisely the same as those conferred upon the colored race by the Fifteenth.”
71
This
makes sense from a textualist perspective, as the Nineteenth Amendment was written as an analogue
to the Fifteenth Amendment.
72
Forty years later in Williams v. Rhodes, the Supreme Court affirmed this
theory of the Nineteenth Amendment in dicta, writing that “[c]learly, the Fifteenth and Nineteenth
Amendments were intended to bar the Federal Government and the States from denying the right to
vote on grounds of race and sex in presidential elections.”
73
It did the same in Gray v. Sanders,
74
and the
Eleventh Circuit recently affirmed this understanding.
75
Whether there is a meaningful difference between these two theories—that the Nineteenth
68
450 F. Supp. 4, 8 (N.D. Ohio 1977) (citing Williams v. Rhodes, 393 U.S. 23, 89 (1968)).
69
See Craig v. Boren, 429 U.S. 190 (1976) (holding that intermediate scrutiny is the proper standard of review for
scrutinizing gender classifications under the Equal Protection Clause).
70
Leser v. Garnett, 258 U.S. 130, 136 (1922).
71
See Opinion of the Justices, 113 A. 603, 616 (Me. 1921).
72
Compare U.S. CONST. amend. XV (“The right of citizens of the United States to vote shall not be denied or abridged
by the United States or by any State on account of race, color, or previous condition of servitude.”), with U.S. CONST. amend.
XIX (“The right of citizens of the United States to vote shall not be denied or abridged by the United States or by any State on
account of sex.”).
73
393 U.S. 23, 29 (1968).
74
372 U.S. 368, 379 (1963) (“The Fifteenth Amendment prohibits a State from denying or abridging a Negro’s right
to vote. The Nineteenth Amendment does the same for women.”).
75
Jones v. Governor of Fla., 975 F.3d 1016, 1042 (11th Cir. 2020) (“Race is never a permissible criterion for
determining the scope of the franchise [under the Fifteenth Amendment]. And this understanding extends to the Nineteenth
Amendment’s prohibition of sex-based voter qualifications.”).
Published by Penn Carey Law: Legal Scholarship Repository, 2021
24 U. PA. J.L. & SOC. CHANGE 4 (2021)
336
Amendment’s protections are coextensive with the Fourteenth Amendment or that the Nineteenth
Amendment’s protections are analogous to those of the Fifteenth Amendment—depends in large part
upon whether the Fifteenth Amendment’s protections are merely coextensive with those of the
Fourteenth Amendment. In Jones v. DeSantis, a federal district court adopted this view, holding that:
The Nineteenth Amendment was an effort to put women on the same level as men
with respect to voting, just as the Fifteenth Amendment was an effort to put African
American men on the same level as white men. . . . As is settled, a claim under the
Fifteenth Amendment requires the same showing of intentional discrimination as
the Fourteenth Amendment’s Equal Protection Clause.
76
Yet, in the few modern cases in which the Supreme Court and Courts of Appeals have offered
a Fifteenth Amendment analysis independent of a Fourteenth Amendment analysis, they have treated
the Fifteenth Amendment as an independent and stronger source of protections beyond those afforded
by the Fourteenth Amendment. In Rice v. Cayetano—the Court’s most recent Fifteenth Amendment
case—the Court struck down a Hawaii statute limiting those who could vote for a certain office on the
basis of ancestry as a violation of the Fifteenth Amendment.
77
The Court explicitly treated the statute
as a racial classification but then noted, in assessing the state’s claim that the Fourteenth Amendment’s
one-person, one-vote command may be in conflict with the demands of the Fifteenth Amendment,
that “[t]he Fifteenth Amendment has independent meaning and force” relative to the Fourteenth
Amendment.
78
Courts of Appeals have also treated the Fifteenth Amendment as an independent source of
voting rights. In Davis v. Guam, for example, the Ninth Circuit elected to strike down racial
classifications on Fifteenth Amendment grounds, rather than Fourteenth Amendment grounds,
79
and
in Jones v. Governor of Florida, the Eleventh Circuit spent considerable energy assessing plaintiffs claims
under the Fourteenth, Fifteenth, and Nineteenth Amendments, offering distinct analyses for each.
80
Assuming the Fifteenth Amendment—and by extension the Nineteenth Amendment
81
provides protections separate from those afforded to voters under the Fourteenth Amendment, the
question remains: what precisely are these protections? In the limited contexts where the Courts of
Appeals have addressed this question, the answer has been absolute. In Davis v. Guam, the Ninth Circuit
described restrictions imposed by the Fifteenth Amendment upon states as “fundamental and
absolute.”
82
Although the Ninth Circuit did not lay out a clear framework for Fifteenth Amendment
challenges, it did note that “[a]s ‘[t]here is no room under the Amendment for the concept that the right
to vote in a particular election can be allocated based on race,’ the levels of scrutiny applied to other
76
462 F. Supp. 3d 1196, 1239 (N.D. Fla. 2020).
77
528 U.S. 495, 499 (2000).
78
Rice v. Cayetano, 528 U.S. 495, 522 (2000).
79
See 932 F.3d 822, 825 (9th Cir. 2019).
80
See generally 975 F.3d at 1029.
81
See id. at 1043 (“The Nineteenth Amendment forbids the use of sex as a voter qualification in the same way [as the
Fifteenth Amendment].”).
82
932 F.3d at 832 (citing Shaw v. Reno, 509 U.S. 630, 639 (1993)).
https://scholarship.law.upenn.edu/jlasc/vol24/iss3/2
TRANSGENDER AND GENDER-NONCONFORMING VOTING RIGHTS AFTER BOSTOCK
337
constitutional restrictions are not pertinent to a race-based franchise limitation.”
83
In other words,
whatever the level of scrutiny the Fourteenth Amendment demands a court apply to a voting regulation
implicating a racial classification, the Fifteenth Amendment demands more: “[o]ur decision makes no
judgment about whether Guam’s targeted interest in the self-determination of its indigenous people is
genuine or compelling. Rather, our obligation is to apply established Fifteenth Amendment principles,
which single out voting restrictions based on race as impermissible whatever their justification.”
84
The Eleventh Circuit reached a similar conclusion last September.
85
Although the case
ultimately upheld the Florida legislature’s severe restrictions on the scope of Amendment 4, which
enfranchised thousands of former felons, the case’s analyses of the Fifteenth Amendment and
Nineteenth Amendment are instructive. The en banc panel interpreted the Fifteenth Amendment, citing
Rice, to stand for the proposition that “[s]tates must set voter qualifications without any regard to
race.”
86
For this reason, according to the panel “[t]he Fifteenth Amendment does not subject race-
based voter qualifications to strict scrutiny—they are per se unconstitutional.”
87
For the panel, treating laws
that trigger the Fifteenth Amendment as per se unconstitutional, rather than evaluating them under
strict scrutiny, “ensures that any argument that a race-based voter qualification is ‘tied rationally to the
fulfillment’ of an important government interest falls on deaf ears.”
88
Importantly, the panel was also
clear that “[t]he Nineteenth Amendment forbids the use of sex as a voter qualification in the same way
[as the Fifteenth Amendment].
89
Thus, based on the Supreme Court’s decision in Rice and decisions by the Courts of Appeals
in Davis and Jones, any regulations that trigger the protections of the Fifteenth and therefore
Nineteenth Amendment should not be evaluated under either intermediate scrutiny or strict scrutiny;
rather, such regulations should be treated as per se unconstitutional. This rule makes it critical to
understand precisely what sorts of regulations would trigger the Amendments’ protections. The next
section explores this question in depth.
C. Triggers for Nineteenth Amendment Protections
While facial gender classifications without a doubt trigger the Nineteenth Amendment, the
Amendment’s protections are not limited to such classifications. The Supreme Court acknowledged in
Rice that the Fifteenth Amendment has been used to strike down voting regulations containing both
“subtle” and “indirect classifications.
90
Although the statute in question in Davis involved a facial
ethnic classification, in that case the Ninth Circuit made clear that courts should be suspicious of
“sophisticated as well as simple-minded modes of discrimination.”
91
To support this proposition, the
83
Id. (quoting Cayetano, 528 U.S. at 523 (emphasis added)).
84
Id. at 843 (emphasis added).
85
Jones v. Governor of Fla., 975 F.3d 1016, 1025 (11th Cir. 2020).
86
Id. at 1043.
87
Id. (emphasis added).
88
Id. at 1043 (11th Cir. 2020) (quoting Cayetano, 528 U.S. at 548 (Ginsburg, J., dissenting) (internal quotation marks
omitted)).
89
Id.
90
Cayetano, 528 U.S. at 514.
91
Davis v. Guam, 932 F.3d 822, 832–33 (9th Cir. 2019) (quoting Gomillion v. Lightfoot, 364 U.S. 339, 342 (1960))
(“Determining whether a law discriminates ‘on account of race’ is not, however, always straightforward. Voting qualifications
Published by Penn Carey Law: Legal Scholarship Repository, 2021
24 U. PA. J.L. & SOC. CHANGE 4 (2021)
338
Ninth Circuit pointed to two additional types of laws that the Supreme Court has found trigger
Fifteenth Amendment protections: laws with facially neutral classifications but passed with racially
discriminatory intent, as the plurality in City of Mobile v. Bolden recognized,
92
and facially neutral laws
applied in a discriminatory manner, as the court recognized in Lassiter v. Northampton County Board of
Elections.
93
Thus, under the Nineteenth Amendment, facially discriminatory laws, laws passed with
sexually discriminatory intent, and facially neutral laws applied in a manner that discriminates on the
basis of sex should all trigger the Amendment’s protections.
The Jones panel provided a similar analysis, yet crucially it added an additional category of
regulations that would trigger the protections of the Fifteenth and Nineteenth Amendment. The en banc
panel confirmed that the Fifteenth Amendment is “powerful enough to ‘remove . . . or render
inoperative’ any suffrage provision in a state constitution that refers to race, even in the absence of
implementing legislation by Congress”
94
—in other words, facial racial classifications. But the panel also
made clear that the Amendment extends to facially neutral laws that inherently implicate a suspect classification
and uniquely burden voters on one side of that classification:
The [Fifteenth] amendment has similar bite even when States impose discriminatory
voting qualifications by facially neutral means. In Guinn, the Supreme Court
invalidated an amendment to the Constitution of Oklahoma that created a literacy
test for voting but exempted from the test any person who was eligible to vote before
the ratification of the Fifteenth Amendment. Although the state constitution
“contain[ed] no express words” limiting the franchise “on account of race, color, or
previous condition of servitude, the grandfather clause “inherently [brought] that
result into existence,” which violated the Fifteenth Amendment.
95
For this category of Fifteenth Amendment cases, the panel ultimately—and importantly—
landed on but-for causation as the trigger for the Amendment’s protections. The panel plainly stated
that “[t]he Fifteenth and Nineteenth Amendments are best understood to forbid any voter qualification
that makes race or sex a but-for cause of the denial of the right to vote.”
96
That is, just as Title VII prohibits but-
that, by their very terms, draw distinctions based on racial characteristics are of course prohibited . . . . But ‘[t]he (Fifteenth)
Amendment nullifies sophisticated as well as simple-minded modes of discrimination. . . . So, in addition to facial racial
distinctions, classifications that are race neutral on their face but racial by design or application violate the Fifteenth
Amendment.”). Cf. Jolicoeur v. Mihaly, 488 P.2d 1, 4 (1971) (assessing a Twenty-Sixth Amendment challenge and writing “[t]he
Twenty-sixth Amendment, like the Twenty-fourth, Nineteenth, and Fifteenth before it, ‘nullifies sophisticated as well as simple-
minded modes of discrimination. It hits onerous procedural requirements which effectively handicap exercise of the franchise . . .
although the abstract right to vote may remain unrestricted.’”) (quoting Lane v. Wilson, 307 U.S. 268, 275 (1939)).
92
See City of Mobile v. Bolden, 446 U.S. 55, 62 (1980) (plurality opinion) (“Our decisions, moreover, have made clear
that action by a State that is racially neutral on its face violates the Fifteenth Amendment only if motivated by a discriminatory
purpose.”). Although this quoted language in Bolden appears to endorse a narrower interpretation of the Fifteenth Amendment
that would only forbid voting laws passed with a racially discriminatory intent, only four justices signed on to this portion of the
opinion.
93
See Lassiter v. Northampton Cnty. Bd. of Elections, 360 U.S. 45, 53 (1959) (“Of course a literacy test, fair on its face,
may be employed to perpetuate that discrimination which the Fifteenth Amendment was designed to uproot.”).
94
Jones v. Governor of Fla., 975 F.3d 1016, 1042 (11th Cir. 2020).
95
Id. (citations omitted).
96
Id. (emphasis added).
https://scholarship.law.upenn.edu/jlasc/vol24/iss3/2
TRANSGENDER AND GENDER-NONCONFORMING VOTING RIGHTS AFTER BOSTOCK
339
for discrimination on the basis of sex and gender identity, so too does the Nineteenth Amendment
prohibit but-for discrimination in voting on the basis of sex and, as we argued in Part I, gender identity.
The panel’s particular formulation—”any voter qualification that makes race or sex a but-for
cause of the denial of the right to vote”
97
—focuses on but-for discrimination that denies the right to
vote. While this may lead one to think that the Nineteenth Amendment does not reach laws that merely
burden the right to vote, the text of the Amendment provides a clear rebuttal. As noted in Part II, the
language of the Nineteenth Amendment reads: “[t]he right of citizens of the United States to vote shall
not be denied or abridged by the United States or by any State on account of sex.”
98
In Fifteenth
Amendment case law, courts have construed the term “abridge” to mean “shorten.”
99
In the little
Nineteenth Amendment case law we have, courts have similarly regarded the Nineteenth Amendment
as extending to regulations that merely “burden the right to vote on the basis of sex.
100
Thus, the Nineteenth Amendment’s protections should be understood to be triggered not
only by regulations passed with sexually discriminatory intent, nor only by neutral laws applied in a
sexually discriminatory manner, but also by “any voter qualification that makes . . . sex a but-for cause
of the denial of the right to vote”
101
or the abridgment or burdening of the right to vote.
102
As laid out
in Part I, these sex-based protections should be understood to encompass analogous gender-based
protections. Any law that triggers these protection should be held per se unconstitutional.
III. BOSTOCK’S IMPLICATIONS ON THE FOURTEENTH AMENDMENT
We recognize that the relative dormancy of the Nineteenth Amendment in voting rights
litigation, and in jurisprudence more broadly, may raise doubts among readers that there is enough
“there there” to sustain our argument. Yet Bostock’s constitutional implications do not stop with the
Nineteenth Amendment. While the textualist logic of Bostock and textual parallels between Title VII
and the Nineteenth Amendment make it an obvious first target, the Bostock Court’s analysis of gender
provides a solid foundation to expand voting rights for transgender and gender-nonconforming voters
via the protections of the Fourteenth Amendment.
To recap Part I, in Bostock the Court recognized that gender identity classifications are sex
classifications—or rather, that one cannot discriminate on the basis of gender identity without also
discriminating on the basis of sex. Since then, courts have already begun to operationalize this logic to
afford transgender individuals the gender protections inherent in the Equal Protection Clause. In Corbitt
v. Taylor, for example, a district court in Alabama recently struck down a state law requiring Alabama
residents to “surgically modify their genitals before they can change the sex designation on their
97
Id.
98
U.S. CONST. amend. XIX (emphasis added).
99
See Reno v. Bossier Par. Sch. Bd., 528 U.S. 320, 333–34 (2000); see also Hasen & Litman, supra note 7, at 39.
100
See, e.g., Graves v. Eubank, 87 So. 587, 588 (Ala. 1921) (interpreting the Nineteenth Amendment to prohibit the
state “placing conditions or burdens upon one [sex] not placed upon the other as a condition precedent to the right to vote.”);
see also Hasen & Litman, supra note 7, at 39 (“[L]aws and procedures diminishing voting on the basis of gender are constitutionally
impermissible [under the Nineteenth Amendment.”).
101
Jones v. Governor of Fla., 975 F.3d 1016, 1042 (11th Cir. 2020).
102
Hasen and Litman reach a similar conclusion by way of a different of analysis. See Hasen & Litman, supra note 7, at
39 (“[T]he term ‘abridgement is consistent with the thick reading of the Amendment as barring laws that have discriminatory
effect on voting power on the basis of gender.”).
Published by Penn Carey Law: Legal Scholarship Repository, 2021
24 U. PA. J.L. & SOC. CHANGE 4 (2021)
340
licenses.”
103
In doing so, the court applied intermediate scrutiny on the theory that “[a]ll state actions
that classify people by sex are subject to the same intermediate scrutiny. The State need not favor or
disfavor men or women to trigger such scrutiny; the classification itself is the trigger.”
104
Civil rights
litigators too are seeking to operationalize this logic, mounting arguments, for example, that
“[d]iscrimination based on sex includes, but is not limited to, discrimination based on gender, gender
nonconformity, transgender status, gender expression, and gender transition.”
105
As noted above, laws containing a gender classification are reviewed under intermediate
scrutiny. To be sustained under intermediate scrutiny, the law must further an important government
interest and must do so through means substantially related to that interest.
106
Separately, challenges to
generally applicable election laws brought under the Fourteenth Amendment are typically evaluated
under Anderson-Burdick review.
107
Under Anderson-Burdick review, “a court evaluating a constitutional
challenge to an election regulation weigh[s] the asserted injury to the right to vote against the ‘precise
interests put forward by the State as justifications for the burden imposed by its rule.’”
108
Then, unless
the court finds the burden to be severe, it should uphold the voting regulation at issue
109
as a
“reasonable, nondiscriminatory restriction”
110
on the right to vote, justified by “the State’s important
regulatory interests.”
111
This applies to “evenhanded restrictions that protect the integrity and reliability
103
Corbitt v. Taylor, No. 2:18cv91-MHT, 2021 WL 142282, at *1 (M.D. Ala. Jan. 15, 2021).
104
Id. at *3.
105
First Amended Complaint at 68, Diamond v. Ward, No. 5:20-cv-00453-MTT (M.D. Ga. Feb. 16, 2021),
https://ccrjustice.org/sites/default/files/attach/2021/02/36_2-16-21_Amended-Complaint_w.pdf [https://perma.cc/UU6P-
XY94] (last visited June 30, 2021).
106
See Craig v. Boren, 429 U.S. 190, 197 (1976) (“To withstand constitutional challenge, previous cases establish that
classifications by gender must serve important governmental objectives and must be substantially related to achievement of those
objectives.”).
107
This test derives from two Supreme Court cases. See Burdick v. Takushi, 504 U.S. 428, 430 (1992) (upholding a
Hawaii law proscribing write-in votes); Anderson v. Celebrezze, 460 U.S. 780, 805–6 (1983) (striking down an Ohio filing deadline
for independent candidates to get on the ballot). For more on Anderson-Burdick review, see Christopher S. Elmendorf, Structuring
Judicial Review of Electoral Mechanics: Explanations and Opportunities, 156 U. PA. L. REV. 313, 316–18 (2007) (providing a thorough
analysis of Anderson-Burdick review); Edward. B. Foley, Due Process, Fair Play, and Excessive Partisanship: A New Principle for Judicial
Review of Election Laws, 84 U. CHI. L. REV. 655 (2017), 674–78 (analyzing Anderson-Burdick review and the doctrinal confusion it
has created).
108
See Crawford v. Marion Cnty. Election Bd., 553 U.S. 181, 190 (2008) (quoting Anderson, 460 U.S. at 789) (majority
and dissent both applying Anderson-Burdick review to a voter ID regulation).
109
See Jamelia N. Morgan, Disparate Impact and Voting Rights: How Objections to Impact-Based Claims Prevent Plaintiffs from
Prevailing in Cases Challenging New Forms of Disenfranchisement, 9 Ala. C.R. & C.L. L. Rev. 93, 157 (2018) (“Unless courts are willing
to characterize the burden on voting as a particularly severe or burdensome restriction, and require the defendant jurisdiction to
demonstrate a narrowly tailored compelling interest, the plaintiff’s claim will typically be rebutted.”).
110
Burdick, 504 U.S. at 434.
111
Id. Many scholars have noted the ways in Anderson-Burdick review untethered the court’s voting rights jurisprudence
from the Warren Court’s more robust voting jurisprudence, giving states greater latitude to enact burdensome and discriminatory
voting regulations. See Joshua S. Sellers, Political Participation, Expressive Association, and Judicial Review, 69 AM. U. L. REV. 1617, 1626
(2020) (“Anderson introduced a less rigorous form of judicial review in the election regulations context.”); Pamela S. Karlan, Undue
Burdens and Potential Opportunities in Voting Rights and Abortion Law, 93 IND. L. J. 139, 145 (2018) (“The retreat in voting rights began
in Burdick v. Takushi. . . . The Court rejected the idea that ‘a law that imposes any burden upon the right to vote must be subject
to strict scrutiny.’”) (quoting Burdick, 504 U.S. at 432).
https://scholarship.law.upenn.edu/jlasc/vol24/iss3/2
TRANSGENDER AND GENDER-NONCONFORMING VOTING RIGHTS AFTER BOSTOCK
341
of the electoral process itself.”
112
The Supreme Court has applied Anderson-Burdick review to challenges to voter ID laws. In
Crawford v. Marion County, a constitutional challenge to Indiana’s voter ID law, the court upheld the law
under Anderson-Burdick review.
113
In doing so, the Court made it clear that Anderson-Burdick review
applies to facially-neutral policies of election administration even if they have a disproportionate impact
on an identifiable group: the Court recognized that the Indiana voter ID laws being challenged would
make it more difficult for certain categories of voters to obtain the requisite ID, yet it decided to
evaluate the laws under Anderson-Burdick review anyway.
114
The burdens imposed by the voter ID law in Crawford differ in important ways from the
burdens imposed on transgender and gender-nonconforming voters by the layering of voter ID laws
on top of strict identity document laws. Specifically, there is a fundamentally different relationship
and a much closer tie—between the burden on voting rights imposed by these laws and a voter’s
identity within a suspect class. The effects of the law challenged in Crawford were felt disproportionately
by certain voters,
115
yet the law was, at least in one sense, “even-handed”: The law did not specifically
require voters of a suspect or non-suspect class to obtain or update an ID because of their identity.
According to the Court, it merely “incidentally” burdened some voters more than others. In advocating
for Anderson-Burdick review, Justice Scalia’s concurring opinion stressed this element of the voter ID
scheme, writing:
[W]hat petitioners view as the law’s several light and heavy burdens are no more than
the different impacts of the single burden that the law uniformly imposes on all
voters. To vote in person in Indiana, everyone must have and present a photo
identification that can be obtained for free. The State draws no classifications, let
alone discriminatory ones . . . .
116
By contrast, laws that jointly require voters to both (1) obtain a form of voter ID that has a
gender marker that accurately conveys a voter’s gender identity and (2) to pay a hefty expense and/or
undergo gender confirmation surgery to update their gender marker operate differently. While in
Crawford the voter ID law—at least in theory—burdened all voters (with some “incidentally” more
burdened than others), laws that at once require an up-to-date gender marker on an ID to vote and
charge voters to change their identity documents—either directly or indirectly via a proof-of-surgery
requirement—uniquely burden voters on one half of a gender classification because the only voters who
will encounter the burden erected by these laws are those whose gender identity differs from that on
their current identification documents.
117
In other words, unlike in Crawford, the burden is triggered by a
voter’s identity within a quasi-suspect class: their transgender or gender-nonconforming identity. That gender
identity places voters on one side of a quasi-suspect classification, triggering the gender-based
112
Crawford, 553 U.S. at 189–90 (quoting Anderson, 460 U.S. at 788).
113
Id.
114
See id. at 205 (Scalia, J. concurring).
115
See id. at 221 n.25 (Ginsburg, J. dissenting) (recognizing that “the burdens of an ID requirement may . . . fall
disproportionately upon racial minorities”).
116
See id. at 205 (Scalia, J. concurring). Separate from this classification issue, the plurality and concurrence also decided
to apply a lower standard of review because the law did not severely burden voting rights. Id. at 204.
117
Cf. Corbitt v. Taylor, No. 2:18cv91-MHT, 2021 WL 142282, at *2 (M.D. Ala. Jan. 15, 2021).
Published by Penn Carey Law: Legal Scholarship Repository, 2021
24 U. PA. J.L. & SOC. CHANGE 4 (2021)
342
protections of the Equal Protection Clause. Unlike in Crawford, there is thus a direct tie between a voter’s
identity within a protected class and the burden experienced by that voter under the laws.
So while laws like these, as in Crawford, are “generally applicable in the narrow sense that all
voters are potentially subject to the requirements and, as in Crawford, the operation of the laws will have
a disproportionate impact on certain voters, the joint operation of these laws goes a step further by
impacting solely—not just disproportionately—voters on one side of a suspect classification. Laws like
these implicate an identity-based classification more strongly than a generally applicable and even-
handed law that has a disproportionate impact on an identifiable group. That classification is a quasi-
suspect classification, deserving of intermediate scrutiny.
Thus, although we believe the Nineteenth Amendment should principally apply to gender-
identity-based barriers to the franchise, we recognize the gravity of Crawford may pull courts away from
evaluating voter ID schemes under the Nineteenth Amendment and towards the Fourteenth
Amendment. Nevertheless, voter ID laws and other election administration laws that uniquely burden
transgender and gender-nonconforming individuals should not be evaluated using Anderson-Burdick
review in as-applied Fourteenth Amendment challenges. Rather, given the now judicially cognizable
gender classification between cisgender and transgender and gender-nonconforming individuals and
the ways in which the combination of strict voter ID laws and strict identity document requirements
burden voters because of their gender identity, such laws should receive at least intermediate scrutiny
under the Fourteenth Amendment.
118
We acknowledge that the analysis above would potentially put the Court’s equal protection
gender jurisprudence in tension with the Nineteenth Amendment, since a voting regulation with a
gender classification might get intermediate scrutiny under the Fourteenth Amendment and also be
treated as per se unconstitutional under the Nineteenth Amendment. In such a case, the demands of
the Nineteenth Amendment should take precedent because in constitutional theory “the specific
governs the general”
119
—that is, where both a general constitutional protection and a specific
constitutional protection overlap, the specific should govern. The Nineteenth Amendment was passed
specifically for the purpose of ensuring that all voters, regardless of sex can participate as equals in the
political process. Therefore, when voting regulations could be analyzed under either the Fourteenth
Amendment or the Nineteenth Amendment, they should principally be assessed under the Nineteenth
Amendment.
Beyond the specific governing the general, there are other important reasons for the
118
There is also a good argument that on the basis of the severity of the burden alone, such regulations should be
evaluated using a higher level of scrutiny than Anderson-Burdick review. In Crawford the court recognized that generally applicable
laws that imposed severe burdens on the right to vote or that imposed “‘excessively burdensome requirements on any class of
voters should be subject to higher scrutiny. Crawford v. Marion Cnty. Election Bd., 553 U.S. 181, 202, 204 (2008) (citing Storer
v. Brown, 415 U.S. 724, 738 (1974)). As laid out in Part IV, in some states transgender and gender-nonconforming voters must
pay considerable expenses and/or undergo gender confirmation surgery to change the gender marker on their ID required to
vote. See infra Part IV. Since courts have been less tolerant of voter ID laws under which voters cannot obtain a free voter ID,
there are good reasons to think that courts would regard laws placing financial burdens between a voter and their free ID with
similar suspicion. See Karen Shanton & Wendy Underhill, Costs of Voter Identification, NATL. CONF. OF STATE LEGISLATURES,
June 2014, at 1-2, https://www.ncsl.org/documents/legismgt/elect/Voter_ID_Costs_June2014.pdf [https://perma.cc/99NY-
G962] (last visited June 30, 2021).
119
See Travis Crum, The Superfluous Fifteenth Amendment?, 114 NW. UNIV. L. REV. 1549, 1566 (2020) (citing Morales v.
Trans World Airlines, Inc., 504 U.S. 374, 384 (1992)) (arguing that Congress’ enforcement powers under the Fifteenth
Amendment should be understood to be distinct and broader than its enforcement powers under the Fourteenth Amendment).
https://scholarship.law.upenn.edu/jlasc/vol24/iss3/2
TRANSGENDER AND GENDER-NONCONFORMING VOTING RIGHTS AFTER BOSTOCK
343
Nineteenth Amendment to take precedent over the Fourteenth Amendment in constitutional
challenges to election laws. In equal protection jurisprudence, regulations using gender classifications
receive only intermediate scrutiny, rather than strict scrutiny, because according to courts, unlike racial
classifications, there are certain situations in which it is normatively superior for courts to probe a
gender classification with less scrutiny than a racial classification. This is because, unlike racial
classifications, which according to the courts are inherently suspect, gender classifications can
sometimes be benign and beneficial to women.
120
Such a rationale simply does not apply to the voting context. As with any racial classification
in the voting context, there are no benign reasons for a state to impose a gender-based regulation in
the voting context. Any such regulation would only restrict or pose obstacles to the exercise of the right
to vote by a certain class of voters on the basis of an aspect of identity that has no bearing on the
capacity to participate in a democracy. As with race-based regulations, we should view any such
regulations with suspicion, and, accordingly, courts should regard them principally as per se
unconstitutional under the Nineteenth Amendment.
IV. ASSESSING A POTENTIAL NINETEENTH AMENDMENT CHALLENGE: VOTER ID
For the reasons laid out in Part I, we believe that the textual analysis offered in Bostock has
clarified those who fall under the protections of the Nineteenth Amendment and expanded the types
of classifications that should receive intermediate scrutiny under the Fourteenth Amendment. The
consequences of such a reading of the Nineteenth and Fourteenth Amendments are momentous, given
both the substantive protections potentially afforded to voters under the Nineteenth and Fourteenth
Amendments as well as the significant challenges that voter ID schemes and restrictive identity
document laws pose to transgender and gender-nonconforming voters. We conclude this article by
providing just one example of the ways in which our two novel constitutional theories could serve as
an important font for the voting rights of transgender and gender-nonconforming voters.
Below, we argue that laws requiring identification documents containing a gender marker in
order to vote and those requiring that voters pay significant economic sums and/or undergo surgery
to change a gender marker on their ID abridge the right to vote. Specifically, when acting together,
these laws create a gender classification that imposes burdens on transgender and gender-
nonconforming voters not imposed on cisgender voters solely because of their gender identity. “[B]ut-
for”
121
the gender identity of the voters, their right to vote would not be “abridged.”
122
The joint
operation of voter ID laws and restrictive identity document laws is thus suitable for challenge,
following Bostock, under the expansive view of the Nineteenth Amendment outlined in Part II and, if
challenged under the Fourteenth Amendment, should be reviewed under intermediate scrutiny as
120
See Kim Shayo Buchanan, The Sex Discount, 57 UCLA L. REV. 1149, 1169 (2010) (“By
choosing intermediate scrutiny of gender classifications over the strict scrutiny advocated by Justice Brennan’s plurality in
Frontiero v. Richardson, the Court presumes that, while some gender classifications are invidious, others are likely benign.”). See also
Melissa Murray, The Equal Rights Amendment: A Century in the Making Symposium Foreword, 43 N.Y.U. REV. OF L. & SOC. CHANGE
HARBINGER 91, 97 (2019) (noting cases in which the Court has upheld benign gender legal classifications under intermediate
scrutiny, including “laws that make it easier for mothers to transmit citizenship to children born out of wedlock in foreign
countries, as well as laws that preclude women from the draft”).
121
Jones v. Governor of Fla., 975 F.3d 1016, 1042 (11th Cir. 2020).
122
U.S. CONST. amend. XIX.
Published by Penn Carey Law: Legal Scholarship Repository, 2021
24 U. PA. J.L. & SOC. CHANGE 4 (2021)
344
argued in Part III.
Voter identification schemes across the country pose a significant threat to the voting rights
of transgender and gender-nonconforming individuals. To cast a ballot once registered to vote—a
hurdle in itself
123
—transgender and gender-nonconforming people must first identify their state’s voter
ID laws and determine whether any of the acceptable forms of identification they have list the correct
gender marker.
124
If none of the voter’s identification documents list the correct gender or name (in
this case, the gender or name other than that assigned to the voter at birth), the voter must then embark
on a lengthy and costly process to update their documents.
125
If the state’s procedures for updating
identification documents are too cumbersome for the voter, the voter risks having to cast a provisional
ballot at the polls, which grants wide discretion to local officials to confirm the validity of a person’s
vote.
126
Voters may also face harassment and humiliation at the hands of election workers and judges
at both steps of the process.
127
A recent study by the Williams Institute estimated that 965,350
transgender people were eligible to vote in the November 2020 general election and that, of that group,
over 378,000 voting-eligible transgender people may have faced barriers to voting due to voter
registration requirements and voter ID laws.
128
To protect these voters from barriers to voting as a
direct result of voter ID and identity document laws, several organizations staffed Election Day hotlines
reserved specifically for transgender voters facing difficulties at the polls.
129
Accounts of harassment
and disenfranchisement are likely to emerge over the coming months.
Thirty-five states had some form of voter ID requirement in place for the 2020 election.
130
123
S. E. JAMES, J. L. HERMAN, S. RANKIN, M. KEISLING, L. MOTTET, & M. ANAFI, THE REPORT OF THE 2015 U.S.
TRANSGENDER SURVEY 232–34 (Nat’l Ctr. for Transgender Equality 2016),
https://transequality.org/sites/default/files/docs/usts/USTS-Full-Report-Dec17.pdf [https://perma.cc/P5WM-9XFW] (last
visited June 30, 2021).
124
TAYLOR N. T. BROWN & JODY L. HERMAN, VOTER ID LAWS AND THEIR ADDED COSTS FOR TRANSGENDER
VOTERS 4 (Williams Inst. 2016), https://williamsinstitute.law.ucla.edu/wp-content/uploads/Trans-Voter-ID-Mar-2016.pdf
[https://perma.cc/D289-6XBG] (last visited June 30, 2021).
125
Id. at 4–5.
126
Id. at 4.
127
See JAMES, HERMAN, RANKIN, KEISLING, MOTTET, & ANAFI, supra note 123, at 232; Scottie Andrew, Why Some
Transgender Voters Have an Even Bigger Challenge to Casting Their Ballots, CNN (Oct. 13, 2020),
https://www.cnn.com/2020/10/13/politics/transgender-voter-suppression-2020-election-trnd/index.html
[https://perma.cc/5HPF-HUZM] (“Ozias, a transgender man from Corpus Christi, Texas, couldn’t afford to legally change his
name or update his ID before he went to vote in state elections in November 2013. He brought his old ID—with a name he no
longer used and a photo that no longer resembled him—to the polls that year. Poll workers grilled him on his identity. They
attempted to stop him from voting . . . .”).
128
KATHRYN O’NEILL & JODY L. HERMAN, THE POTENTIAL IMPACT OF VOTER IDENTIFICATION LAWS ON
TRANSGENDER VOTERS IN THE 2020 GENERAL ELECTION 1–2 (Williams Inst. 2020),
https://williamsinstitute.law.ucla.edu/wp-content/uploads/Trans-Voter-ID-Feb-2020.pdf [https://perma.cc/ML2B-G8AA]
(last visited June 30, 2021).
129
See, e.g., TRANS VOTER PROTECTION HOTLINE, https://outvoters.org/ [https://perma.cc/DS6P-HVH2] (last
visited June 30, 2021); Protecting Trans Voters: Call the National Trans Protection Hotline, NATL CTR. FOR TRANSGENDER EQUALITY
BLOG (Nov. 2, 2020), https://transequality.org/blog/protecting-trans-voters-call-the-national-trans-voter-protection-hotline
[https://perma.cc/R97E-67EP].
130
Voter Identification Requirements | Voter ID Laws, NATL CONF. OF STATE LEGISLATURES (Aug. 25, 2020), https://
www.ncsl.org/research/elections-and-campaigns/voter-id.aspx [https://perma.cc/9DQN-YUN9].
https://scholarship.law.upenn.edu/jlasc/vol24/iss3/2
TRANSGENDER AND GENDER-NONCONFORMING VOTING RIGHTS AFTER BOSTOCK
345
Most states require only non-photo identification, like bank statements or lease documents.
131
Eighteen
states require photo identification but offer an avenue for those without acceptable identification to
cast a ballot that will be counted, either by a poll worker’s voucher or provisional ballot.
132
Twelve of
these states have “non-strict” voter ID schemes, so called because they do not require voters lacking
acceptable ID to take additional action after election day in order to have their ballot counted.
133
The
six “strict” voter ID states require either government-issued photo or non-photo identification, and
they require voters to take additional steps after the election to have a provisional ballot counted should
they not show the required identification when they cast their ballot in person.
134
Outside of the voting context, identification requirements for a range of activities pose
obstacles for transgender and gender-nonconforming individuals. In many states, it is difficult and
expensive to obtain identification documents that reflect a person’s gender if that gender is different
than the one assigned to them at birth.
135
In fact, in a 2015 report by the National Center for
Transgender Equality, sixty-eight percent of transgender respondents said that none of their
identification documents listed their correct name and gender.
136
The legal gender and name change
process can cost up to $2,000 in certain cases, which may make the process inaccessible for many.
137
In nine states, including Georgia, gender confirmation surgery—a costly, intensive procedure that many
transgender and gender-nonconforming people choose not to pursue
138
—is required
139
in order to
change the gender marker on a state ID or birth certificate.
140
In many states, the process involves
paying court fees, undergoing a background check, and collecting and submitting medical
documentation.
141
In the voting context, transgender and gender-nonconforming voters are subjected to
harassment and stigmatic harms when casting a ballot. Identification requirements often result in
transgender and gender-nonconforming people being turned away at the polls.
142
When poll workers
examine the voter registration rolls and match voters information to the information on the
131
Id.
132
Id.
133
Id.
134
Id.
135
O’NEILL & HERMAN, supra note 128, at 5.
136
JAMES, HERMAN, RANKIN, KEISLING, MOTTET, & ANAFI, supra note 234, at 82.
137
Id. at 84.
138
BROWN & HERMAN, supra note 124, at 3 (noting that not every transgender person undertakes the same steps to
transition from their sex assigned at birth to their gender). In addition, not every transgender or gender-nonconforming person
wishes to undergo surgical transition.
139
Georgia, Kansas, and Wisconsin permit court orders of gender change in lieu of a physician letter confirming gender
confirmation surgery. Id. at 14. However, in some states, including Georgia, obtaining such a court order of gender change
requires proof of gender confirmation surgery. See infra note 134.
140
ID Documents Center | Georgia, NATL CTR. FOR TRANSGENDER EQUALITY, (May 2020),
https://transequality.org/documents/state/georgia [https://perma.cc/A2PH-TVC5] (last visited June 30, 2021).
141
Scottie Andrew, Why Some Transgender Voters Have an Even Bigger Challenge to Casting Their Ballots, CNN (Oct. 13, 2020),
https://www.cnn.com/2020/10/13/politics/transgender-voter-suppression-2020-election-trnd/index.html
[https://perma.cc/S8A8-6FAU].
142
See O’Neill & Herman, supra note 128, at 2.
Published by Penn Carey Law: Legal Scholarship Repository, 2021
24 U. PA. J.L. & SOC. CHANGE 4 (2021)
346
identification they present, poll workers may—and often do
143
—find that a transgender or gender-
nonconforming voter’s name, gender marker, and appearance do not match, providing a reason to turn
away the voter.
144
Even in the least restrictive voter ID states, poll workers have asked for ID and
subsequently turned away voters because their faces have not “matched” their names on voter rolls.
145
In some states, poll workers have been actively encouraged to turn away transgender and gender-
nonconforming voters.
146
Although poll workers are not statutorily required to turn voters away on this
basis, and may not even be permitted to do so,
147
in practice they do so with some frequency.
148
In
strict voter ID states, turning away these voters leaves them with no recourse: if a denied voter does
not have identification that presents a name and gender marker determined by a county registrar to
match their appearance—likely because of the obstacles associated with obtaining that
identification
149
—they will not be able to take the required steps to have a provisional vote counted.
150
The combination of strict voter ID laws and identity document laws in many states
accordingly poses a severe threat to the voting rights of many transgender and gender-nonconforming
individuals. One such state is Georgia, where government-issued photo identification is required—all
of which, except military or governmental employer identification cards, require a voter to indicate their
sex or gender
151
—provisional ballots are not accepted without demonstration of ID within three days
of the election,
152
and the state requires that individuals show proof of gender confirmation surgery in
order to update the gender marker on their birth certificate or state identification.
153
143
Sarah Fielding, ‘The System is Unfair’: US Trans and Non-Binary People Hit by Voting Barriers, GUARDIAN (JUNE 16,
2020), https://www.theguardian.com/us-news/2020/jun/16/trans-people-voting-november-election [https://perma.cc/JHP3-
UZ3E].
144
See O’Neill & Herman, supra note 128, at 6.
145
See Fielding, supra note 137 (reporting that a precinct judge requested ID from a woman in North Carolina, a state
that does not require ID to vote, because “[her] face d[id]n’t match [her] name.”).
146
See Voting Rights Watch, Ready to Vote? Rampant Suppression Threatens Already Tight Race, NATION (Nov. 2, 2012),
https://www.thenation.com/article/archive/ready-vote-rampant-suppression-threatens-already-tight-race/ [https://perma.cc/
KR5N-2B8Q] (noting the use of transphobic images in a training manual for poll workers that suggest transgender and gender-
nonconforming voters are committing voter fraud).
147
See #VotingWhileTrans Guide, TRANSFORM THE VOTE (2020), https://transformthevote.org/voting-resources
[https://perma.cc/4P82-2ZPU] (last visited June 30, 2021).
148
See Fielding, supra note 143.
149
Legal gender and name changes can cost up to $500. JAMES, HERMAN, RANKIN, KEISLING, MOTTET, & ANAFI,
supra note 123, at 82 (reporting thirty-five percent of trans people surveyed who did not try to change their legal name cited the
cost as their primary barrier). People looking to effectuate a gender and name change must, in most states, file paperwork with
the court. Often, the paperwork is not easy to complete on one’s own and may require attorney representation. Trans Legal Services
Network, NATL CTR. FOR TRANSGENDER EQUALITY (Aug. 26, 2019), https://transequality.org/issues/resources/trans-legal-
services-network-directory [https://perma.cc/CD22-QWWJ]. In some states, gender confirmation surgery is a prerequisite for
obtaining a gender marker change. NATL CTR. FOR TRANSGENDER EQUALITY, supra note 140. As a result of the ongoing
COVID-19 pandemic, many courts nationwide are temporarily closed and are not accepting name or gender change petitions.
Id.
150
NATL CONF. OF STATE LEGISLATURES, supra note 136.
151
See id. Georgia law requires voters to present a state-issued photo ID, a Georgia drivers license, a state- or county-
issued voter ID card, a U.S. passport, federal government employee ID card, or a military or tribal ID. Id.
152
Id.
153
Identity Document Laws and Policies, MOVEMENT ADVANCEMENT PROJECT,
https://scholarship.law.upenn.edu/jlasc/vol24/iss3/2
TRANSGENDER AND GENDER-NONCONFORMING VOTING RIGHTS AFTER BOSTOCK
347
We believe that statutory schemes like those in Georgia are vulnerable under the Nineteenth
Amendment and Fourteenth Amendment. A challenge to the combined effect of two or more statutory
regulations is appropriate when the “joint operation” of the laws in question, but not the operation of
each law on its own, results in an unconstitutional set of circumstances.
154
Here, the joint operation of
Georgia’s strict voter ID laws and highly restrictive identity document requirements places a significant
financial, logistical, and emotional burden on certain categories of voters solely because of their gender
identity. From the perspective of the Court’s current voter ID jurisprudence, considering strict voter
ID laws in isolation, anyone who can obtain a photo or non-photo identification document in the state
where they are registered to vote is presumed by the Court to be able to overcome the burden imposed
by these laws.
155
For the purposes of the argument here, the requirement that voters present
identification is not, by itself, unconstitutional, and was upheld by the Court in Crawford.
156
But layering
strict voter ID regimes atop strict state statutory requirements for altering the gender marker on one’s
identity documents presents the constitutional problem.
Operating in tandem, voter ID laws and laws restricting changes to gender markers construct
a fine mesh through which only cisgender voters can pass unburdened. Transgender and gender-
nonconforming voters, in order to comply with both laws requirements, must choose whether to
undergo the time, expense, and emotional cost of gender confirmation surgery in order to obtain an
ID that accurately reflects their gender identity or use an ID that does not reflect their gender identity
and risk being turned away at the polls on that basis. The result is a de facto gender classification scheme
that operates, in practice, to burden any voter whose gender identity differs from that listed on their
requisite ID. Other similarly situated voters are not similarly burdened—in fact they are not burdened
at all. Thus, but-for their gender identity, these voters would not be subject to this abridgement of their
right to vote. In this sense, as laid out in Part III, the operation of laws like Georgia’s as applied to
transgender and gender-nonconforming voters are distinguishable from that of the Indiana law in
Crawford.
Strange as it may sound at first blush, we believe the best analogy may be Guinn v. United States.
Recall from Part II that, in Guinn, the Supreme Court struck down an Oklahoma constitutional scheme,
excepting voters enfranchised prior to the passage of the Fifteenth Amendment from having to pass
an otherwise generally applicable literacy test. The court struck down the provision as a violation of the
Fifteenth Amendment because the “neutral” law inherently and uniquely burdened newly enfranchised
Black men.
Over one hundred years later, transgender and gender-nonconforming voters face an
analogous problem. In Guinn, a generally applicable law created a “generally applicable” burden: all
https://www.lgbtmap.org/equality-maps/identity_document_laws [https://perma.cc/3ZDY-LY5X] (last visited June 30,
2021). See also NATL CTR. FOR TRANSGENDER EQUALITY, supra note 140.
154
See, e.g., Kane v. Fortson, 369 F. Supp. 1342, 1343 (N.D. Ga. 1973) (recognizing plaintiff’s Nineteenth Amendment
claim that “[t]he joint operation of [several provisions of the] Georgia [Code] . . . , in so far as it establishes an irrebuttable
presumption that the domicile and residence of a married woman is that of her husband, and thereby prevents her from
registering to vote in Georgia, violates the [N]ineteenth [A]mendment of the Constitution of the United States.”).
155
Of course, contrary to the Court’s understanding in Crawford, strict voter ID laws do present severe obstacles and
adverse consequences for a number of eligible voters. See, e.g., John Kuk, Zoltan Hajnal & Nazita Lajevardi, A Disproportionate
Burden: Strict Voter Identification Laws and Minority Turnout, POLITICS, GROUPS, AND IDENTITIES (2020). These obstacles are well-
documented and are outside the scope of this paper.
156
Crawford v. Marion Cty. Election Bd., 553, U.S. 185, 204 (2008).
Published by Penn Carey Law: Legal Scholarship Repository, 2021
24 U. PA. J.L. & SOC. CHANGE 4 (2021)
348
voters were required to pass a literacy test, but those eligible to vote on January 1, 1866 were exempt
from the test because they were grandfathered in.
157
Yet because of the timing of the grandfather clause,
the only voters actually subject to the burden of a literacy test were Black male voters newly
enfranchised by the Fifteenth Amendment.
158
Similarly, under Georgia’s scheme, a set of generally
applicable laws creates a “generally applicable” burden: all voters must have a requisite voter ID with
an up-to-date gender marker, and in order to update their ID with a different gender identity, they must
submit proof of gender confirmation surgery. Yet, like in Guinn, in practice the only voters actually
subject to this obstacle are voters of a protected class: here transgender and gender-nonconforming
voters. Thus, in both cases, laws are structured in facially neutral ways that not only disproportionately
burden members of suspect classes, but—crucially—uniquely burden members of suspect classes. In
this way, just as in Guinn the grandfather clause “‘contain[ed] no express words limiting the franchise
‘on account of race, color, or previous condition of servitude,’”
159
yet “‘inherently [brought] that result
into existence,’” violating the Fifteenth Amendment, schemes like Georgia’s “‘contain no express
words limiting the franchise ‘on account of [sex],’” yet “‘inherently [bring] that result into existence,’”
160
violating the Nineteenth Amendment.
The analogy remains just as clearer if one flips the presumption of the grandfather clause, as
the panel did in Jones. In Jones, the panel noted that Guinn stood for the proposition that “the Fifteenth
Amendment forb[ids the state from] discriminat[ing] within [a] class of illiterate non-voters by
exempting only white citizens from literacy tests.
161
From this point of view, the proper way to view
the grandfather clause is not as an additional burden on Black voters. Instead, one should view the
grandfather clause as an exemption of white voters from a requirement. Georgia’s scheme arguably
operates in the same way: cisgender voters are exempted from paying a kind of “gender fee” that
transgender and gender-nonconforming voters must pay solely by virtue of their gender identity.
As presented in Part II, laws that uniquely burden voters on one side of a gender classification
trigger the Nineteenth Amendment’s protections. The regulatory scheme outlined above thus should
be regarded as per se unconstitutional under the Nineteenth Amendment.
If evaluated under the Fourteenth Amendment, the result is the same by way of a different
analysis. While election security is plausibly an important government interest, it would be unreasonable
for a court to hold that the expenses associated with changing identity documents—and, where
mandated by law, requiring voters to undergo surgery—are substantially related to election security. In-
person voter fraud is extraordinarily rare—in-person fraud somehow enabled by placing fewer
economic and stigmatic burdens between gender-transitioning voters and the ballot box is ludicrous.
Thus, under either of our theories, the laws should be held unconstitutional.
157
Guinn v. United States, 238 U.S. 347, 357 (1913).
158
Id. at 365.
159
Jones v. Governor of Fla., 975 F.3d 1016, 1042 (11th Cir. 2020) (quoting Guinn, 238 U.S. at 364–65).
160
Id. (quoting Guinn, 238 U.S. at 364–65).
161
Id. at 1040.
https://scholarship.law.upenn.edu/jlasc/vol24/iss3/2
TRANSGENDER AND GENDER-NONCONFORMING VOTING RIGHTS AFTER BOSTOCK
349
CONCLUSION
Transgender and gender-nonconforming voting rights are an urgent matter. It is long past
time for transgender and gender-nonconforming voters to be accorded equal dignity and respect as
equal participants in the political process. The joint operation of voter ID laws and restrictive laws on
changing identity documents reifies unjust gender norms, subjects voters to harassment and
intimidation by bigots, and disenfranchises thousands of voters every year, who either cannot jump
through the hoops necessary to obtain an acceptable form of voter ID with an accurate gender marker
or, in view of these barriers to voting, discourage transgender and gender-nonconforming voters from
participating in the political process at all. This article has tried to use the holding and analysis of Bostock
as an opportunity to forge a path to tear down these unjust laws.
Published by Penn Carey Law: Legal Scholarship Repository, 2021